• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 209
  • 32
  • 13
  • 9
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 5
  • 4
  • 2
  • 2
  • 2
  • Tagged with
  • 331
  • 331
  • 63
  • 51
  • 38
  • 34
  • 32
  • 29
  • 26
  • 22
  • 22
  • 19
  • 17
  • 17
  • 17
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
1

A historical approach to the theory of groups

Barbeau, Alice Mae, January 1900 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Wisconsin--Madison, 1968. / Typescript. Vita. eContent provider-neutral record in process. Description based on print version record. Includes bibliographical references.
2

The relationship between cohesiveness and productivity in small, leaderless, discussion groups

Stokes, Rosemary January 1954 (has links)
The present study was designed to investigate the relationship between cohesiveness and productivity in small groups. A review of the pertinent literature revealed various approaches to the problem and conflicting findings concerning it. This study was confined to investigating such a relationship in a leaderless, discussion-type setting. Groups representative of three degrees of cohesiveness were investigated. The three types of groups were as follows: "Highly structured", -a group in which each member is chosen by every other member, and all choices are confined within the group. (All choices were made on a sociometric basis.) "Semi-structured", -a group in which the majority of members choose other members, but the majority of choices are not mutual, and all choices are not confined within the group. "Unstructured", -a group in which no choices occur within the group. On the basis of findings from other studies conducted in similar settings two hypotheses were advanced: 1. That a group which is either partially or highly structured will be more productive in carrying out a working project than a group which is relatively unstructured. 2. That a semi-structured group will be more productive in carrying out a working project than a highly structured group. The study was carried out at a summer camp consisting of seventy-one girls aged twelve to fourteen. From the camp groups of four girls each were chosen to represent the three degrees of cohesive-ness listed above. These groups were equated as far as possible for age, motivation, and social acceptance. Each group was asked to prepare and present an original skit. Group interaction was observed in order to gain fuller and more comprehensive data concerning the relationship under investigation. Group productivity was assessed by means of judges’ ratings of the performances. These ratings indicated a direct relationship between cohesiveness and productivity in this experiment, such that the more cohesive a group the greater its productivity. Analysis of the interaction data suggested that productivity was also affected by time and by the type of interaction present, both of which may or may not be related to cohesiveness. Further investigation is indicated. / Arts, Faculty of / Psychology, Department of / Graduate
3

Organizational variables in relation to efficiency: a comparative study of four watershed organizations

Slutker, Jack Bert. January 1963 (has links)
Call number: LD2668 .T4 1963 S64 / Master of Science
4

Sociometric structuring of four organizational units in relation to size and efficiency

Langford, Charles Clinton. January 1965 (has links)
Call number: LD2668 .T4 1965 L27 / Master of Science
5

Does the social exist?

Werbeloff, Jason 08 August 2014 (has links)
In this thesis I question whether social phenomena exist. Since social groups are perhaps the most widely recognised category of social phenomena, I focus my discussion on social groups. First I elucidate our common-sense intuitions about social groups. Thereafter, I distinguish between two problems: specifying the relation among the members of a social group (the individual-individual problem), and specifying the relation between social groups and their members (the social-individual problem). I argue that the individual-individual and social-individual problems comprise the core concerns of social ontology, at least insofar as social ontology is applied to social groups. I then examine a number of possible solutions to the individual-individual problem, and argue that none of these positions convincingly captures our common-sense intuitions about social groups. I divide these solutions into Objectivist and Subjectivist accounts. Objectivist accounts of social groups exclude reference to the reflexive mental states of the individuals underlying the group, and focus instead on the patterns of interactions among group members, observable from a non-member’s perspective. I argue that Objectivist accounts, including Elster’s transactional account, the organic account, and the teleological account of social groups, are unable to capture adequately the distinction between a mere aggregate and a social group because they exclude reference to reflexive mental states, rendering the accounts vulnerable to a number of counterexamples. By contrast, Subjectivist positions, including Sartre’s account, Gilbert’s plural subject theory, and Searle’s constructionism, hold that reflexive mental states provide the principle that unifies a collection of individuals into a social group. Subjectivists, however, are unable to account for the importance of the history of social phenomena. Thereafter I consider affirmative solutions to the social-individual problem, or positions that hold that social groups exist. These positions are divided into non-reductive and reductive accounts. Non-reductive accounts, including Social Dualism and Non-Reductive Individualism, hold that social groups are logically or conceptually distinct from the individuals that comprise them. Social Dualists posit that social groups and their members are distinct entities, while Non-Reductive Individualists hold that social properties are distinct from individualistic properties. I argue that Social Dualism problematically reifies the social, while Non-Reductive Individualism is unable to maintain the dependence of the social on the individual without collapsing into a reductive account. Reductionists hold that social groups are identical with their members, or with the intra-relations among their members. Logical Individualists hold that this identity is conceptual: the concept of a social group is the concept of a collection of individuals. Type Individualists claims that types of social groups are identical with types of members (or types of member intra-relations). And Social Functionalists hold that social groups are just phenomena with a certain function, and those functional phenomena are in turn instantiated by individuals. I argue that none of the reductive accounts are successful, however: Logical Individualism cannot account for the holism of the social, Type Individualism faces the problem of multiple realisation, and Social Functionalists cannot adequately individuate groups diachronically. Finally, I tentatively support an alternative, negative solution to the individual-individual and social-individual problems: Eliminative Individualism. Eliminative Individualism is the position that social phenomena do not exist, that Folk Sociology is a radically false and misleading theory, and that social terms have no referent. I discuss a number of strategies for eliminating social phenomena, ultimately providing a psychological and neurological explanation that I argue might be used to explain away the appearance of social groups. That is, I make a case for the possibility that we can explain away beliefs in social groups the way we explain away paranormal, or errant religious beliefs. Finally, I argue that “thick” social phenomena, such as the wisdom of the crowds and the unintended consequences of intended action, may be explained using reason-based, statistical and possibly network-based explanations. I conclude that Eliminative Individualism, although it faces certain challenges, is worthy of serious attention as a contender to affirmative social ontologies in the literature.
6

The Psychology of procedural justice: a test of process control effects in groups. / Group process control effects

January 1991 (has links)
Yuk-Fai Au. / Running title: Group process control effects. / Thesis (M.Phil.)--Chinese University of Hong Kong, 1991. / Bibliography: leaves 45-50. / Acknow1edgements --- p.2 / Abstract --- p.3 / Introduction --- p.4 / Method --- p.15 / Results --- p.23 / Discussion --- p.35 / References --- p.45 / Tables --- p.51 / Footnotes --- p.57 / Figure --- p.58 / Appendices --- p.59
7

VERBAL PATTERNS OF AN INFORMAL GROUP WHICH EMPLOYS DEMOCRATIC PROCESSES

Bishop, Towne Charles, 1939- January 1972 (has links)
No description available.
8

The examination of faculty subcultures within institutions of higher education

Rodriguez, Donna Ashe 08 1900 (has links)
No description available.
9

Similarity of cognitive structures as a determinant of clique formation /

Pritchard, Monica Carmel. January 1973 (has links) (PDF)
Thesis (B.A. Hons.) -- University of Adelaide, Department of Psychology, 1974.
10

Social mix : a worthwhile planning concept?.

Lambert, Raymond Dean. January 1977 (has links) (PDF)
Thesis (M.T.P. 1978) from the Department of Architecture, University of Adelaide.

Page generated in 0.0281 seconds