• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 16
  • 3
  • 3
  • 1
  • Tagged with
  • 32
  • 32
  • 10
  • 9
  • 5
  • 5
  • 4
  • 3
  • 3
  • 3
  • 3
  • 3
  • 2
  • 2
  • 2
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
1

Abstraction in art

Grants, Arvid John January 1963 (has links)
I. Statement of the problem. The subject of abstraction is of very great importance not only in science, in logic and mathematics, or in the theory of knowledge, but also in art. It might be said that abstraction is a process in which consideration is given to some aspect or feature of a complex whole to the neglect of the remainder; but this statement is both too vague and too restrictive to cover all the cases in which abstraction is commonly said to occur. In order to avoid here the mistake involved in the "paradox of analysis", exemplified by saying that "centaur" and "medusa" mean the same thing (since there never was either the one nor the other), it is necessary to recognize that the abstractness of a work of art is something quite different from that of science, mathematics, logic or epistemology. This difference does not lie in the meaning of "abstraction", but in the purpose for which abstraction is used. In both art and science abstraction is the recognition of a relational structure or "form" apart from the specific thing in which it is exemplified. But the word "form" has different meanings in various fields. A logician or mathematician may question what sense it makes to call anything "form" except the logical form of discourse, the structure of propositions expressed either in ordinary language or in the refined symbolism of the pure sciences; an artist, in his turn, may ask how one can speak of the "form" as something invisible and intangible, as for example, the series of natural numbers, or elaborate mathematical equations, when for him "form" must be sensible. The problem of abstraction in art is complicated further by the fact that, although, (speaking of painting and sculpture) abstraction is achieved by the use of the technical device of schematized shapes (usually called "abstractions"), contemporary art critics and artists are divided as to how abstraction "works". Roughly speaking, they are divided into two camps, and the defence of each position rests on a different view of the world. One theory of art experience presupposes a world consisting of mysterious entities which, by interaction with another equally mysterious entity, the ego, produce sensations. Configurations of these sensations result in artistic form in two basic varieties: one, the naturalistic, the product of an "affirmative" attitude toward the world, is bound to concrete experiences, in fact, to physical things; the other, the non-naturalistic or "abstract", the consequence of "negative" attitude toward the world, essentially artificial and difficult, results from modern man's "dread of space" or "fear of nothingness", etc. I shall call this theory in its two aspects the "existentialist theory" of art experience. Another theory of art experience takes a rational view of the universe (recognizing, however, certain limits to man's reason) and proposes that that experience is closely bound up with sense perception and cognition analyzable in logical terms. In this tradition abstraction is viewed as an intellectual process, capable of being discussed in terms other than "positive" and "negative". Accordingly, the work of art is so constructed that its categorical elements are in common with reality, and combined to represent a coherent structure. Abstraction in art is defined as the constant experimenting with syntactical combinations of the language elements of that special type of language which is the actual work of art. I shall call this the "rational theory" of art experience. Discussion of this view of abstraction will involve the discussion of what is meant by "work of art", "internal" and "external" logic of the structure of works of art, what I mean by such banalities as "reality" and "truth". In a word, the discussion will turn upon the meaning and purpose of all artistic activity. II. Method of investigation. In discussing the problem outlined above I am not going to declare which of the two views of the world is right, which is wrong, but I will support the theory which appears to me the more exciting and which seems to afford the more satisfactory explanation of what is meant by abstraction in art. In doing it I shall use as supporting arguments my own conclusions about works of recent and contemporary masters along with quotations from their manifestos, autobiographies and other writings, as well as the ideas of critics and historians about them. Also I shall not shrink from using classical sources, because, to my mind, the phenomenon of abstraction cannot be reserved for contemporary art alone. It cannot be denied, however, that the use of the adjective "abstract", synonymous with "modern", "non-objective", "non-representational", etc., has become quite frequent and has acquired special importance since the turn of the century. The term "abstract art" is generally understood as denoting cubism, futurism and expressionism, and demonstrating a common effort on the part of contemporary artists, musicians and writers on the one hand, and scientists, philosophers and mathematicians on the other, to solve similar or identical problems. Therefore some attention will be directed to contemporary developments in these disciplines along with art. In my treatment of the subject I shall stress the philosophical implications rather than the historical significance. Above all, my approach will be determined by the influence upon me of the Cambridge philosophers and the adherents of philosophical movements related to them, but especially the writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein will be seen to have inspired the concepts developed in this thesis. III. General conclusions. The general conclusions arrived at in this thesis might be stated in the form of the following principles: (a) All art is abstract. (b) In art the aim is to depict reality. (c) A work of art is constructed so that its categorical elements are in common with reality and combined to represent a coherent structure (correspondence theory). (d) A work of art is an interpreted fact, and thus represents a prototype truly or falsely. Truth is arrived at when inquiry is stopped. (e) Since the elements of a work of art are combined in a definite way, its truth value will be determined upon the examination of the "internal" logic of its structure, together with the "key of interpretation." (f) It makes sense to say that there are many realities and one way of interpreting them, just as it makes sense to say that there is one reality and many ways of interpreting it. (g) Abstraction in art is the constant experimenting with syntactical combinations of the "language elements" of that special type of language which is the actual work of art. / Arts, Faculty of / Art History, Visual Art and Theory, Department of / Graduate
2

The emergence of abstraction in the work of Ben Nicholson 1919-1939 /

Guest-Griffith, Alison. January 1900 (has links)
Thesis (M.A.)--Ohio State University. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 125-129). Available online via OhioLINK's ETD Center
3

Otherworldly goods

Johnson, Grant, January 2002 (has links)
Thesis (M.F.A.)--West Virginia University, 2002. / Title from document title page. Document formatted into pages; contains vi, 32 p. : ill. (some col.). Includes sound file in the mp3 audio format. Vita. Includes abstract. Includes bibliographical references (p. 29).
4

A group of non-representational paintings

Moyle, Michael James, 1933- January 1966 (has links)
No description available.
5

A study of abstractions in drawing with the aid of photographs to produce both symmetrical and asymmetrical compostions

Meuninck, Thomas C. January 1970 (has links)
This study was composed of several large detailed drawings of forms from nature. The drawings were total abstractions of organic forms that had been photographed. The basic composition was structures-of ovals, rectangles and circles with various combinations of the three. With in the basic structures the writer subdivided the areas manipulating organic free forms with reliefs of white special areas.
6

Abstract reality the alienating gaze : this exegesis is submitted to Auckland University of Technology for the degree of Masters in Art and Design, December 2005.

Matheson, Clare. January 2005 (has links) (PDF)
Exegesis (MA--Art and Design) -- Auckland University of Technology, 2005. / Also held in print (68 leaves : col. ill. ; 30 cm.) in Wellesley Theses Collection. (T 700.458 MAT)
7

Experiments in abstract expressionistic painting

McCabe, James Edward, 1924- January 1955 (has links)
No description available.
8

Influences in American painting 1963 with a presentation of the thesis paintings

Britton, John A. January 1964 (has links)
Call number: LD2668 .T4 1964 B86
9

The Contemporary Art Society of NSW and the theory and production of contemporary abstraction in Australia, 1947-1961

Whitehouse, Denise Mary, 1947- January 1999 (has links)
Abstract not available
10

The use of white areas in painting

Hupp, Frederick Duis, 1938- January 1966 (has links)
No description available.

Page generated in 0.0726 seconds