Spelling suggestions: "subject:"rrt anda morals"" "subject:"rrt ando morals""
1 |
Art, morality and ethics : philosophical interpretationsYan, Hektor King Tak January 2000 (has links)
No description available.
|
2 |
Two sides of the same mind: How our beliefs about the artist's moral mind influence the way we respond to the artistic mindHawley, Angelina January 2013 (has links)
Thesis advisor: Ellen Winner / In two studies I examine how contextual information about the moral mind of the artist affects both children's and adults' response to works of art. Study 1 examined liking ratings of artworks as well as utilitarian objects. Factors varied were whether the items were said to have been made vs. owned by people of negative vs. positive moral character. Forty adults, 20 7-8-year-olds, and 23 4-5-year-olds were shown 12 artworks and 12 utilitarian objects and were asked to indicate on a 7-point scale how much they liked each one. Each item was presented as either owned or made by a person of positive or negative moral character. Moral character was predicted to affect liking ratings, with artworks expected to be affected more by the moral character of the maker than the owner, and utilitarian objects expected to be affected more by the moral character of the owner than the maker. Moral character had a significant effect on liking ratings: both artworks and utilitarian objects were liked less when believed to have been owned or made by someone of negative rather than positive moral character, demonstrating a moral contagion effect. Contrary to prediction, believing that an artwork was made by a person of negative moral character did not depress liking ratings more than believing that the artwork was owned by an artist of negative character. But consistent with prediction, believing that a utilitarian object was owned by a person of negative moral character depressed liking ratings more than believing that the object was made by someone of negative character. These findings held for all three age groups. Study 2 examined both liking and evaluative judgment ratings for two kinds of artworks: those whose content is related to the artist's moral character and those whose content is unrelated to the artist's character. Sixty-seven adults, 24 7-8 year-olds, and 23 4-5-year-olds were shown 12 representational paintings and were asked to indicate on a 7-point scale how much they liked each one and how good they thought each one was. Moral character was expected to affect both liking and evaluative judgment ratings, and content-related works were expected to be liked less than content unrelated works for artists of negative moral character; no effect of content-relatedness was expected for the putatively more objective evaluative judgments. Results replicated the moral contagion effect found in Study 1 for liking as well as judgment ratings with negative moral character linked to lower ratings than positive moral character. As predicted, liking ratings were lower for related than unrelated content for works by artists of negative moral character. Contrary to prediction, the same result held for works by artists of positive moral character. Evaluative judgment ratings were not affected by whether the content was related or unrelated in the case of artists of negative character (as predicted), but for artists of positive character, unrelated images were judged better. Children ages 7-8 behaved like adults for both liking and judgment ratings. Children ages 4-5 liked and judged as better the images with unrelated content for both mean and nice artists. Thus, adults and children ages 7-8-years old liked images more when the artist's moral mind was not visibly displayed but judged the related/unrelated images as equally good--indicating that the artistic mind (displayed through the arrangement of the composition, colors etc.) was more important for evaluations than was the moral mind. For 4-5-year-olds, preferences did not diverge from evaluative judgments. Thus, what they liked was what they thought was good, and moral "right" was equivalent to aesthetic "right". Taken together, results lead to the conclusion that artworks are affected by moral contagion, but moral contagion affects liking more strongly than it affects evaluative judgment. / Thesis (PhD) — Boston College, 2013. / Submitted to: Boston College. Graduate School of Arts and Sciences. / Discipline: Psychology.
|
3 |
The ethics of assisted dyingBagley, Elizbeth Ann 28 July 2016 (has links)
No description available.
|
4 |
Otnoshenīi︠a︡ iskusstva k nauki︠e︡ i nravstvennosti dissertatsīi︠a︡ na stepenʹ magistra filosofīi /Bobrov, Evgenīĭ, January 1895 (has links)
Thesis (master's)--Imp. I︠U︡rʹevskiĭ un-t, 1895. / Includes bibliographical references.
|
5 |
The Victorian morality of art an analysis of Ruskin's esthetic,Ladd, Henry, January 1932 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--Columbia University, 1932. / Vita., 1 ℓ. inserted between p. 404-405. Published also without thesis note. Bibliography at end of each chapter.
|
6 |
A broad aesthetic : beauty, truth, and goodnessRisser, Rita January 2003 (has links)
The dissertation A Broad Aesthetic: beauty, truth, and goodness , takes into consideration three distinct but related aspects of aesthetics: perception, appreciation, and evaluation (beauty, truth, and goodness respectively). A central concern in an avowedly broad aesthetics is to attend, equally, to the bounds of the experiences or activities under consideration. Hence, this dissertation is a exploration of the breadth, but also of the limits, of certain aesthetic experiences and art-based activities (e.g., the appreciation and evaluation of artworks). It is a consideration of what shapes these experiences, and, also of the delimitation of these experiences and activities. Section one (beauty) considers the nature of aesthetic perception, and the limits of its reach. Section two (truth), looks at the role of style, both its scope and limit, in the classification and appreciation of a certain genre of fine writing (philosophy), as well as a certain genre of filmmaking (the documentary). Section three (goodness) looks at the role and relevance of moral values and interests in the evaluation, as well as in the curation, of artworks.
|
7 |
The Victorian morality of art an analysis of Ruskin's esthetic,Ladd, Henry, January 1932 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--Columbia University, 1932. / Vita., 1 ℓ. inserted between p. 404-405. Published also without thesis note. Bibliography at end of each chapter.
|
8 |
The reaction against Ruskin in art criticism art and morality,Yount, Charles Allen, January 1941 (has links)
Part of Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Chicago, 1938. / Reproduced from type-written copy. "Private edition, distributed by the University of Chicago libraries, Chicago, Illinois." Includes bibliographical references.
|
9 |
A broad aesthetic : beauty, truth, and goodnessRisser, Rita January 2003 (has links)
No description available.
|
10 |
Titian's Rape of Europa : the intersection of ethics and aesthetics /Eaton, Anne Wescott. January 2003 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Chicago, Dept. of Art History and Dept. of Philosophy, Aug. 2003. / Includes bibliographical references. Also available on the Internet.
|
Page generated in 0.0861 seconds