• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 11
  • 8
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 3
  • 2
  • 2
  • 1
  • 1
  • Tagged with
  • 37
  • 14
  • 14
  • 12
  • 8
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 6
  • 4
  • 4
  • 4
  • 4
  • 3
  • 3
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
1

Avicenne et la médecine Arabe. Joseph Eddé.

Eddé, Joseph. January 1889 (has links)
Th.--Méd.--Paris, 1889. / Paris - 1889 - vol. 9. N ° 182.
2

Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Mathematik Avicenna als Mathematiker, besonders die planimetrischen Bücher seiner Euklidübersetzung /

Lokotsch, Karl, January 1912 (has links)
Thesis (doctoral)--Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität zu Bonn, 1912. / Vita.
3

Avicenna als Mathematiker, besonders die planimetrischen Bücher seiner Euklidübersetzung ...

Lokotsch, Karl, January 1912 (has links)
Inaug.-diss.--Bonn (Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität). / Lebenslauf.
4

The Metaphysics of Agency: Avicenna and his Legacy

Richardson, Kara 26 February 2009 (has links)
This dissertation begins with the Islamic philosopher Avicenna, who transforms Aristotle’s conception of the efficient cause in the Metaphysics of his Shifā’. Its first goal is to examine the arguments which constitute Avicenna’s metaphysical account of agency. Its second goal is to examine Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents that arise in connection with his view. In its final chapter, it relates Medieval debates about efficient causality to Descartes’ account of the causal powers of bodies. One of the original features of Avicenna’s account of agency is his argument for the claim that the existence of contingent things requires an efficient cause. This aspect of his view was influential in the Latin West. Avicenna also holds that the cause of the existence of contingent things is an incorporeal principle, which he describes as an agent who “bestows forms”. I argue that Avicenna fails to resolve the tension between this claim and his commitment to an Aristotelian account of generation. This failure sets the stage for Avicenna’s role in Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents in cases of generation. Both Aquinas and Suarez attribute to Avicenna the view that generation requires the creation of form. They argue that generation occurs through natural processes. Suarez’s view includes the claim that the substantial form of a substance is an immediate efficient cause of its actions. Suarez defends this claim against other Aristotelians, who hold that a substantial form gives being to a composite substance as a formal cause and that the actions of substances depend directly on their accidents alone. Descartes claims in his letter to Regius of January 1642 that it is absurd to hold that substantial forms are immediate principles of action. He thinks that bodies act in virtue of their modes. Here Descartes sides with those Aristotelians who hold that the actions of substances depend directly on their accidents alone. I argue that this aspect of Descartes’ view tells against Daniel Garber’s claim that his denial of substantial forms deprives bodies of causal efficacy.
5

The Metaphysics of Agency: Avicenna and his Legacy

Richardson, Kara 26 February 2009 (has links)
This dissertation begins with the Islamic philosopher Avicenna, who transforms Aristotle’s conception of the efficient cause in the Metaphysics of his Shifā’. Its first goal is to examine the arguments which constitute Avicenna’s metaphysical account of agency. Its second goal is to examine Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents that arise in connection with his view. In its final chapter, it relates Medieval debates about efficient causality to Descartes’ account of the causal powers of bodies. One of the original features of Avicenna’s account of agency is his argument for the claim that the existence of contingent things requires an efficient cause. This aspect of his view was influential in the Latin West. Avicenna also holds that the cause of the existence of contingent things is an incorporeal principle, which he describes as an agent who “bestows forms”. I argue that Avicenna fails to resolve the tension between this claim and his commitment to an Aristotelian account of generation. This failure sets the stage for Avicenna’s role in Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents in cases of generation. Both Aquinas and Suarez attribute to Avicenna the view that generation requires the creation of form. They argue that generation occurs through natural processes. Suarez’s view includes the claim that the substantial form of a substance is an immediate efficient cause of its actions. Suarez defends this claim against other Aristotelians, who hold that a substantial form gives being to a composite substance as a formal cause and that the actions of substances depend directly on their accidents alone. Descartes claims in his letter to Regius of January 1642 that it is absurd to hold that substantial forms are immediate principles of action. He thinks that bodies act in virtue of their modes. Here Descartes sides with those Aristotelians who hold that the actions of substances depend directly on their accidents alone. I argue that this aspect of Descartes’ view tells against Daniel Garber’s claim that his denial of substantial forms deprives bodies of causal efficacy.
6

Avicenne et la médecine arabe /

Eddé, Joseph, Unknown Date (has links)
Thesis (doctoral)--Faculté médicine de Paris, 1889, no. 182. / "Thèse pour le doctorat en médecine; présentée et soutenue le mercredi, avril 1889, à 1 heure ...."--T.p.
7

Die Rezeption der Philosophie des Aristoteles im Islam als Beispiel die Rezeption der Seelenlehre des Aristoteles bei Ibn Sīnās Buch ('Ilm al-nafs: Die Wissenschaft der Seele) /

Samir Gara, Nizar. Unknown Date (has links) (PDF)
Universiẗat, Diss., 2003--Heidelberg.
8

The concept of imagination in Aristotle and Avicenna /

Portelli, John P. (John Peter) January 1979 (has links)
No description available.
9

The concept of imagination in Aristotle and Avicenna /

Portelli, John P. (John Peter) January 1979 (has links)
No description available.
10

Ibn Sīnā's thought on the "perfect man" : the role of the faculties of the soul

Yusuf, Arbaʾiyah. January 1994 (has links)
This thesis is a study of Ibn Sin a's concept of the Perfect Man, which is studied here with reference to the role of the faculties of the soul. Chapter I is a brief introduction to Ibn Sina's life and his intellectual background. Chapter II studies Ibn Sin a's views on human existence, the human body and the human soul. In the section dealing with the the human soul, the faculties of the soul are elaborated at length. Chapter III discusses Ibn Sin a's concept of the Perfect Man, a person who has reached the highest position which corresponds to the acquired intellect. This chapter also discusses Ibn Sin a's view of the role of the faculties of the soul in attaining to the position of perfection.

Page generated in 0.0477 seconds