• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 2522
  • 1006
  • 245
  • 206
  • 205
  • 186
  • 73
  • 52
  • 40
  • 40
  • 40
  • 40
  • 40
  • 39
  • 28
  • Tagged with
  • 5566
  • 1507
  • 719
  • 659
  • 497
  • 484
  • 421
  • 387
  • 372
  • 365
  • 365
  • 356
  • 355
  • 347
  • 341
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
351

Prvky logiky na základní škole / The elements of logic at basic school

ZEMANOVÁ, Jana January 2010 (has links)
Introduction of diploma work obtains comprehensive inventory of informations from sententional calculus theory, which correspond to problems that are mentioned in examples in diploma work. These teoretical knowledge regarding to needs of work are mainly analysed on secondary mathematics grade, marginally intervene in problems of college logic. Practical part is a task collection for children in infant school and evaluation of their succes in solving examples. I gave chosen examples to children twice. First time at first lesson, where children expresss their opinions to possibilities of problem solution. These opinions weren´t revised. Next time children made the same examples at last lesson after all preparatory exercises. There were seen progress in childrens argumentation close to information about results. Not until this lessons were children acquainted with correct results. In last part of diploma work I mention my experiences and knowlegde about logic for children and some advices for teachers and parents how to work and evolve children´s logic.
352

Artificial intelligence and uncertainty in power system operation

Bell, K. R. W. January 1995 (has links)
No description available.
353

Condition monitoring of fluid power systems using artificial neural networks

Hsu, Cheng-Yu January 1995 (has links)
No description available.
354

The nature of implication

McGechie, J. E. January 1965 (has links)
No description available.
355

The synthetic a priori

Radford, Colin January 1964 (has links)
No description available.
356

Rules of truth for modal logic

Makinson, David Clement January 1965 (has links)
No description available.
357

Logical Generics and Gay Identity

January 2012 (has links)
abstract: Gays identity is usually cast in generics--statements about an indeterminate number of members in a given category. Sometimes these generic statements often get built up into folk definitions, vague and imprecise ways to talk about objects. Other times generics get co-opted into authentic definitions, definitions that pick out a few traits and assert that real members of the class have these traits and members that do not are simply members by a technicality. I assess how we adopt these generic traits into our language and what are the ramifications of using generic traits as a social identity. I analyze the use of authentic definitions in Queer Theory, particularly Michael Warner's use of authentic traits to define a normative Queer identity. I do not just simply focus on what are the effects, but how these folk or authentic definitions gain currency and, furthermore, how can they be changed. I conclude with an analytic account of what it means to be gay and argue that such an account will undercut many of the problems associated with folk or authentic definitions about being gay. / Dissertation/Thesis / M.A. Philosophy 2012
358

Logic and objects : language, application and implementation

McCabe, Francis Gregory Christopher January 1989 (has links)
No description available.
359

Constraints of Binary Simple Homogeneous Structures

Rönchen, Philipp January 2018 (has links)
No description available.
360

What Can You Say? Measuring the Expressive Power of Languages

Kocurek, Alexander William 21 November 2018 (has links)
<p> There are many different ways to talk about the world. Some ways of talking are more expressive than others&mdash;that is, they enable us to say more things about the world. But what exactly does this mean? When is one language able to express more about the world than another? In my dissertation, I systematically investigate different ways of answering this question and develop a formal theory of expressive power. In doing so, I show how these investigations help to clarify the role that expressive power plays within debates in metaphysics, logic, and the philosophy of language.</p><p> When we attempt to describe the world, we are trying to distinguish the way things are from all the many ways things could have been&mdash;in other words, we are trying to locate ourselves within a region of logical space. According to this picture, languages can be thought of as ways of carving logical space or, more formally, as maps from sentences to classes of models. For example, the language of first-order logic is just a mapping from first-order formulas to model-assignment pairs that satisfy those formulas. Almost all formal languages discussed in metaphysics and logic, as well as many of those discussed in natural language semantics, can be characterized in this way. </p><p> Using this picture of language, I analyze two different approaches to defining expressive power, each of which is motivated by different roles a language can play in a debate. One role a language can play is to divide and organize a shared conception of logical space. If two languages share the same conception of logical space (i.e., are defined over the same class of models), then one can compare the expressive power of these languages by comparing how finely they carve logical space. This is the approach commonly employed, for instance, in debates over tense and modality, such as the primitivism-reductionism debate.</p><p> But a second role languages can play in a debate is to advance a conception or theory of logical space itself. For example, consider the debate between perdurantism, which claims that objects persist through time by having temporal parts located throughout that time, and endurantism, which claims that objects persist through time by being wholly present at that time. A natural thought about this debate is that perdurantism and endurantism are simply alternative but equally good descriptions of the world rather than competing theories. Whenever the endurantist says, for instance, that an object is red at time <i> t</i>, the perdurantist can say that the object&rsquo;s temporal part at <i>t</i> is red. On this view, one should conceive of perdurantism and endurantism not as theories picking out disjoint regions of logical space, but as theories offering alternative conceptions of logical space: one in which persistence through time is analogous to location in space and one in which it is not. A similar distinction applies to other metaphysical debates, such as the mereological debate between universalism and nihilism.</p><p> If two theories propose incommensurable conceptions of logical space, we can still compare their expressive power utilizing the notion of a translation, which acts as a correlation between points in logical space that preserves the language&rsquo;s inferential connections. I build a formal theory of translation that explores different ways of making this notion precise. I then apply this theory to two metaphysical debates, viz., the debate over whether composite objects exist and the debate over how objects persist through time. This allows us to get a clearer picture of the sense in which these debates can be viewed as genuine.</p><p>

Page generated in 0.0686 seconds