• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 298
  • 98
  • 80
  • 48
  • 19
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 6
  • 6
  • 4
  • 3
  • 3
  • 2
  • 2
  • Tagged with
  • 622
  • 278
  • 171
  • 107
  • 75
  • 39
  • 37
  • 36
  • 36
  • 35
  • 32
  • 30
  • 30
  • 30
  • 30
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
271

George Maciunas and the Art of Paperwork

Chamberlain, James Colby January 2016 (has links)
This dissertation focuses on the role of George Maciunas as “chairman” of the neo-avant-garde movement Fluxus. Its introductory chapter provides an overview and assessment of Fluxus scholarship, and advances the argument that Maciunas established an intersection between post-Cage aesthetics and postwar administration. The succeeding chapters situate Maciunas’s work in relation to apparatuses regulating education, circulation, production, and health care. Taking as its primary objects Maciunas’s “paperwork”—his visually striking charts, newsletters, card files, architectural plans, and other documents—this study shows how Maciunas employed administrative techniques to build the infrastructure for Fluxus’s collective practice and, concurrently, drew on Fluxus’s aesthetic tactics to disrupt or evade state regulation. Chapter two, “Card Files & Charts,” reconstructs how Maciunas’s training in the professions of architecture and art history was applied to organizing Fluxus’s publications and concerts; Chapter three, “Newsletters & Postcards,” traces Maciunas’s maintenance of an international Fluxus network via the postal service; Chapter four, “Registrations & Catalogs,” reveals how Maciunas codified Fluxus’s negotiation of individual and collective authorship within the legal framework of US copyright law; and, finally, Chapter five, “Prescriptions,” locates in Maciunas’s performances a body marked by medical administration.
272

The national state of emergency

Bureau of Information 06 1900 (has links)
On 12 June 1986, at a joint sitting of the three houses of Parliament, the State President declared a National State of Emergency. In his speech he said: “. . .the sporadic instances of violence have once again begun to increase and have taken on such proportions that I am of the opinion that the ordinary laws of the land at present on the statute book are inadequate to enable the Government to ensure the security of the public and to maintain public order.” What were the State President’s reasons for declaring the State of Emergency? Was the Government’s action justified? What of the rule of law? Has the National State of Emergency achieved its objectives? When will the National State of Emergency be lifted?
273

The biochemical genetics of man / edited by D. J. H. Brock, O. Mayo

Brock, D. J. H., Mayo, Oliver, joint author January 1978 (has links)
Includes bibliographies and indexes / xvi, 832 p. : / Title page, contents and abstract only. The complete thesis in print form is available from the University Library.
274

Electoral despotism in Kenya : land, patronage and resistance in the multi-party context

Klopp, Jacqueline M. January 2001 (has links)
In Africa, the new electoral freedoms of the 1990s often ushered in not less but more violence and corruption. Somewhat paradoxically, democratization appeared to lead to greater despotism. Current theories of democratic transitions fail to adequately explain this negative "fall out". On the one hand, by focusing on formal institutional change, most transitions theory marginalizes the "informal" politics of patronage and violence. On the other hand, theorists of "informal" politics tend to assume that formal institutional change does not impinge on patrimonial dynamics. This thesis explains how the advent of electoral freedom challenges patrimonialism and, in the process, deepens local despotism. By a careful look at the Kenyan case, this thesis argues that the re-introduction of multiple political parties posed a genuine challenge to highest level patronage networks. This challenge consisted of "patronage inflation": competitive elections escalated demands for and promises of patronage just as international conditionalities and economic difficulties led to a decline in traditional supplies of patronage. Further, with multiple political parties, voters gained bargaining power to demand both resources and accountability. A critique of patrimonialism emerged into the public realm, particularly from those who had lost out in the spoils system, the growing numbers of poor and landless. These challenges were met by counter-strategies on the part of those most set to lose by a turnover in elections. With the introduction of alternative political parties, President Moi and key patronage bosses instigated localized but electorally beneficial violence in the form of "ethnic clashes". In their struggle to maintain patrimonial dominance, they also increasingly turned to less internationally scrutinized public lands as a patronage resource, leading to increasing and increasingly violent "land grabbing". This triggered counter mobilizations which aimed at reasserting local co
275

Op weg na 'n christelike logika : 'n studie van enkele vraagstukke in die logika met besondere aandag aan D.H.Th. Vollenhoven se visie van 'n christelike logika / Nicolaas Theodor van der Merwe

Van der Merwe, Nicolaas Theodor January 1958 (has links)
This study furnishes some results of an investigation to ascertain whether the possibility of a Christian logic can be maintained as a meaningful question. This problem seems to be enmeshed in a complex encompassing the problem of Christian science* as such. Whether the possibility of a Christian logic is maintained or denied, at any rate this implies a positive standpoint towards the problem of a Christian logic. Some general remarks having been made in an introductory chapter, the main aspects bearing on the background of different points of view towards logic are presented in Chapter II. <1> The general philosophical conception adopted seems to be of importance with a view to the formation of a conception of logic in at least and especially two respects. <a> Philosophical trends have a marked influence on the view taken of logic. As far as modern philosophy is concerned, one can point to the differences appertaining to logic, its character, and the domain accorded to logic as science, its place in the cosmic reality, etc., differences which become evident in the conceptions of, for example, Descartes, Arnauld & Nicole, Kant, Opzoomer, Heymans, Bolland, Dewey, Bergson and Heidegger. Whereas Dewey, Bergson and Heidegger move in an irrationalistic direction, the first mentioned six philosophers bear evidence of a rationalistic point of view. The idealistic conception of Kant differs from the scientialism of a Descartes and the practicalism of the writers of The Port Ro*al Logic; the difference can be traced to the fact that Kant lends .the divergent solutions furnished by scientialism and practicalism to a unity, which ascribes to the ~ human perceptive faculty two functions, a theoretical and practical; theoretical reason and practical reason are autonomous, each in its particular sphere. The more recent rationalism of an Opzoomer, Heymans and Bolland, keeps to the rationalistic main lines but takes the a priori's of autonomous reason in a dynamic-active sense by laying stress on the scientific methods. Positivism advanced the first solution in this direction, overestimating scientific theory in a scientialistic spirit, with the result that the practical existence is viewed in the light of science. The positivism of a Comte and Opzoomer finds an antipode in the neo-positivism of, for instance, Dilthey, Wundt and Heymans, laying stress on the practical aspect. And then the neoidealism of Cassirer, Bosanquet, Bolland and others bridges the opposition between the positivistic and nee-positivistic conceptions. The far-reaching influence of rationalistic conceptions encountered a serious set-back on account of the increasing importance attached to the se-called critique of science and especially the rise of irrationalistic conceptions. Irrationalism accepts reason in a rationalistic sense, but limits its validity and importance to a specific sphere. The pragQatism of James and Dewey, for instance, supports science only in so far as it furthers practical purposes: one has to obey reason in order to experiment, but the important point is exactly the fact that one is busy experimenting on account of a need bearing on practical life. A second trend, the "philosophy of life" which had an eminent exponent in Bergson, emphasizes the importance of "life" (taken in an organicpsychovitalistic sense) instead of practical utility, and therefore accentuates intuition in contrast to the symbolic operational method of intelligence (which "belong to the domain of logic). And finally existentialistically-minded philosophers champion the cause of human existence, of the individual concrete situation. It is pointed out that these differences in philosophical conception result in different points of view taken of logic. <b> Secondly the specific type of philosophical point of view is an ontological factor of supreme importance in the realisation of a conception of logic. Kant and Hegel, for instance, both advance an idealistic conception, but differ as to the type of philosophical point of view; for Hegel attaches himself to a contradictory type whereas Kant propounds an "ennoetic" conception which regards the sensations as furnishing the material for the forms of the intellect, that is to say, the intellect has the sensations as contents of the mind. Moreover I may refer to the interaction-theory of a Descartes and the instrumentistic point of view of a Bergson or the psychomonistic type represented by a Heymans, etc. Each particular type of philosophical conception involves a specific cosmology and anthropology, and results in a particular conception of logic and the problems of this branch of science. <2> In addition to the above mentioned ontological matters, it is necessary to point separately to the importance of epistemological factors for one's conception of logic. This point is illustrated by enumerating some basic problems of a theory of knowledge and explaining a few points in greater detail, for instance, <a> the possibility and suppositions of knowledge; <b> the analysis of knowledge (including the essence, character and kinds of knowledge), the formation of knowledge, the purpose of knowledge and the unity of knowledge (including limits and scope of knowledge, the partial nature and coherence of knowledge); and <c> the validity of knowledge (including knowledge and law, knowledge and value, as well as the reliability of knowledge). <3> In yet another respect different points of view may arise, viz. according to the opinion held as to logic as science, its character and domain, and the investigation of the logical field. There is, for instance, a trend in logic which attempts to approach the field of logic from that of mathematics, and on the other hand some logicians undertake the task of studying the basic principles of mathematics with logic as the starting-point. Moreover, also the points of view of psychologism in logic (Sigwart) and Husserl’s reaction against this trend, tend to show that the scientific determination of the field of investigation bears testimony to the fact that the logician cannot afford to neglect matters which can be traced to <a> different attitudes in theory of science, and <b > different points of view in regard to the field of investigation. <4> Lastly the suggestion may be offered that one-sided stressing of one or more of the different factors of importance (mentioned above) as such, may also result in different conceptions of logic. * * * Up to this point no attention has been paid to the possibility of the Christian conviction, the Christian "life and world-view", etc., as an important factor in the formation of a conception of logic. Chapter III gives a general survey of the points of view taken on logic in a Christian atmosphere. <1> A Christian logic is an utter impossibility; this is the first standpoint taken as to this problem. This, point of view comprises, however, various subordinate solutions of the problem. <a> Some argue that as far as the importance and implications of Christianity are concerned, Christianity is confined to divine worship and this does not bear on logic in any way whatsoever. <b> Others acknowledge the importance of Christianity for divine worship, and add: for daily practical life too --- although in no wise for science and therefore not for logic. <c> A third solution accepts the significance of Christianity for a section of science, for instance <i> as far as theology is concerned, <ii> and also for philosophy, <iii> and perhaps in some respects for other branches of science (e.g. sociology, ethnology, the science of history, etc.) but at any rate not as far as logic is concerned. <2> On the other hand some scientists, inspired by the reformational concept of Calvin, maintain that Christianity, that the Christian view of cosmos and man, the Christian approach to scientific matters, etc., must be esteemed a factor of importance so far as the conception of science as such is concerned, and that moreover it is imperative that all scientific investigations be undertaken in the light of the revelation (in Holy Scripture); for this reason among others the idea of a Christian logic is not absurd. This thesis can be elucidated by mentioning some contributions to a Christian logic, for instance, <a> A. Kuyper's opinion that science is of two kinds because humanity is of two kinds, those regarding the cosmos as normal and those who take into account the reality of the fall of man in Adam, and therefore acknowledge the fact that an act of interference on the part of God is necessary to put the cosmos again in a correct relation to Him. On account of this difference Kuyper therefore maintains the existence of a Christian and non Christian science. As the fact of sin dit not affect the formal activity of thinking, according to Kuyper, he states that the palingenesis does not cause any difference in this respect; therefore only one kind of logic exists --- a Christian logic. <b> S.O. Los indicates the necessity of a Christian logic by stating that the Calvinistic principles ought to find application in every section of science, not excluding logic. A Christian logic takes into account the principles of Holy Scripture and brings them to bear upon scientific studies. <c> H.G. Stoker's conception of the cosmos as a created coherent diversity implies i n t era 1 i a that the field of logic has an irreducible, unique character of its own, but the logical sphere is part of a comprehensive totality in which all diversity is given in a coherent complex. Because it is a radical diversity, it is unlike the psychical, lingual or ethical sphere, and therefore the logical sphere may not be reduced to any other diversity nor isolated from the diversity with which it constitutes a totality. On account of the fact that cosmic reality is a created diversity, it is not autonomous nor self-sufficient; a Christian logic therefore naturally opposes the dogma of the autonomy of thought.<d> C. Van Til points out that whereas the facts and laws with which logic is concerned, are not detached from their being created, the facts and laws of logic too are not self-sufficient, but part of created reality; accordingly it is imperative that the Christian truths (of, for instance, creation, fall of man into sin, and redemption in Jesus Christ in the communion of the Holy Spirit) be acknowledged from the very beginning. Indeed, as Van Til explains in detail, no part of Christianity remains intact when once the Arminian logic is allowed to run its course. <e> K. Schilder puts forward various considerations bearing on the impossibility of a formal or neutral logic, and states that logic has a foundation in fundamental philosophical ideas, on account of which a Hegelian, Fiahtian and Calvinist have different conceptions of logic; moreover, logic is not detached from other sciences, and in no science can one find one's way without a standpoint in faith. <f> H. Dooyeweerd's "philosophy of the cosmonomic idea" states and illustrates in various respects both the possibility and necessity of a Christian logic. Especially his theory of the nodal spheres each subjected to its own law, discloses an insight of great depth concerning the logical sphere as a modal aspect of cosmic reality, having the numerical and spatial aspects, the aspect of mathematical movement, the aspect of physical energy, of organic life and of psychical feeling as substratum spheres and the historical and linguistic aspects, the aspect of social intercourse, the economic, the aesthetic, the jural, the moral aspects and the aspect of faith as superstratum spheres. In its modal nucleus each sphere enjoys a sovereignty in its own sphere and differs from every other modal aspect; on account of retrocipations each sphere coheres with every previous sphere in the cosmic order and by means of anticipations with the superstratum spheres, thus presenting also a universality in its own sphere. The variable phenomena of each sphere function subjected to a law of their own, for instance, in the logical sphere judgements are subjected to the logical (analytical) law; accordingly this subject is treated as the theory of the spheres of law --- a really important milestone on the way towards a Christian logic, particularly so, as it has proved to be exceptionally useful in determining the characteristic nature of the logical sphere. <g> D.H.Th. Vollenhoven has established the cardinal data of a Christian logic and acquired an insight into such various points of importance for the problem of a Christian logic, that it is considered necessary to treat thereof in a separate chapter. * * * The first section of chapter IV is given to a general survey of the more important writings of Vollenhoven in so far as they contributed towards his conception of a Christian logic. An attempt is made to show how Vollenhoven arrived at his final conception. This section is also intended to furnish the basis for an interpretation of his conception, which follows in the succeeding parts of chapter IV. <1 > <a> Ontology presents an insight into the difference in the being of God, law and cosmos. God is the Sovereign who created the cosmos and put his law to the cosmos. Only God is sovereign, i.e. not subjected to the law. It is only of the law that one can say that it obtains (for that which is subjected to the law); and the being of the cosmos exists in its being subjected to. the law. <b > The word "law" can be taken in three different senses: as structural (modal) law, as the commandment of love, and as positive law. <c> The being of the cosmos displays a diversity of created subjects, heavenly and earthly. <d> By temporarily disregarding the essentials in which man differs from other "things", it is possible to investigate the being of the thing. It is necessary to distinguish the being of the subject and the object, both being subjected to the law, but in different respects. Both have to be investigated as to the modal (universal) differences and to the individual differences, as well as their particular relations and the bonds between modal differences (retrocipations and anticipations) and between individual differences (coherences). An object is a complex having a subject as the bearer of object-functions, attributes such as colour, warmth, etc.; although being more complex than the subject, subject and object have this in common that they are both subjected to the law. <e> The structure of man is even more complex. Beside modal differences and individual differences (having this specific individual characteristic and not that, on account of which this judgement differs from that judgment --- although they do-not differ modally as both are logical), the difference in direction of his functions (good or bad) is of extreme importance as far as the being of man is concerned. For the different modal functions constitute the frame for the activities of man, and therefore the logical sphere is called the logical function. The activities of the heart of man (prefunctional) are, as it were, sent into a specific functional channel; and this activity is directed by the heart in a twofold exit, namely for better or worse. <f> The structure of the realms (man, animal, plant and mineral) brings us to the genetic bond; and <g> as to the structure of mankind two points are worth mentioning, viz. <i> the bonds of community (their character, diversity and mutual relation) and <ii> religion as the covenant between God, the Creator of heaven and earth, and man. <h > After the particular relation between heaven and earth has been treated, the bond between God, law and cosmos demands attention. <2> Theory of knowledge is distinct from ontology but nevertheless presupposes a close relation. <a> The theory of human knowledge is discussed in two main sections: <i> the structure of the non-scientific cognition (including its suppositions; the knowable; the activity of learning-to-know; the result of knowing; and the bond between the result of knowing and the activity of learning, the knowable, and the norm of learning-to-know! and secondly the development of the non-scientific cognition), and <ii> the structure of the scientific cognition (including firstly the cognition in particular scientists method and the diversity of scientific methods in particular science, the analysable for particular sciences, and the result of scientific cognition in particular sciences; and secondly the scientific cognition of nonparticular sciences as, for instance, philosophy); <b> the theory of science investigates particular sciences• and non-particular sciences; and c > methodology studies the problem of method as such, as well as in relation to the different sciences, not excluding logic. <3> Under logic is discussed <a> fundamental philosophical questions, including those of <i> philosophy of the logical field which discloses an insight into the logical sphere of law --- which logic has to investigate --( including in particular the question of what the logical modality is and how the logical aspect is present in that which subsists gnostically),and <ii> philosophy of logic (including, the problem of logic as a science and that of its relation to philosophy). <b> Under the general structure of the analytical (logical) sphere attention is paid to <i> the analytical law and <ii> the analytically subjected, viz. the analytical subjects (including the analytical activity, and the result of this activity: concept and judgment) and the analytical objects (i.e. the• analytical aspect of all the sub analytical); furthermore the bond between analytical subject and object, and lastly the bond between the analytical law and the analytically subjected, as well as the bond between God, analytical law and the analytically subjected. Under the concept is discussed the concept as such, the division of concepts and the particular relations of concepts. The theory of judgment likewise avails itself of these three themes for treating judgment. Chapter V investigates some problems of a more particular nature in the domain of logic; the investigation has had to be restricted to three subjects. <1> The analytical (logical) law. <a> Firstly the question is considered whether an analytical law exists, and it is pointed out that logicians who do give attention to this question usually stress one-sidedly the importance of either the analysable or the analytical activity or the result of thinking (the thought). <b > As far as the sense of the analytical law is concerned, a point of particular importance is Vollenhoven's insight that the analytical law is <i> specifically an analytical (and no nonanalytical, e.g. a mathematical) law, <ii> a structural law, 1. e. a modal law, and <iii> as law, the boundary between God and cosmos. <c> As to the contents of the analytical law, some critical remarks are made about the conception of e.g. Welton &Monahan, and reference is made to the importance and consequences of Vollenhoven's synopsis of the contents of the analytical law: "analyse well the analysable, whatever it may be". <d> The discussion of the question whether the analytical law can or must be considered as being formal, touches a few facets of the problem and gives some arguments for the supposition that it is not formal. <e> Ontology (stating the fundamental distinction between the being of God, law and cosmos) appears of cardinal importance also in respect to the question whether the analytical law be .considered a norm. <f> Finally attention is drawn to fallacies, And the supposition is advanced that one's conception of the analytical law determines in important respects one's view held as to fallacies. Fallacies seem to be due chiefly to the following three causes: <i> by disobeying the analytical norm, <ii > by reason of the fact that the substratum-functions of the logical function fail and <iii> on account of "wickedness of heart". <2> With reference to R. Robinson some points of importance concerning the problem of definition are discussed. The attitude is taken that definition is a specific kind of judgment, viz. a judgment in which the predicate does not analyse or evaluate the subject of the judgment, but delimits the sphere and scope of the subject, determines it, defines it, that is to say: attributes a predicate to the subject of a judgment with a scientific purpose. Definition can be given of concepts, or words, or the contents of words or of concepts, or the meaning of words. Especially important is the fact that the theory about definition presupposes a specific category theory; accordingly a Christian standpoint adopted in scientific study results in a different point of view taken towards definition. Lastly may be mentioned. that the difference between scientific and non-scientific definition ought not be neglected. <3> The comprehensive problem of the division of judgments likewise indicates that a Christian standpoint in science (logic) does not impede or hamper the investigation of the field of logic --- in this case the division of judgments ---- but on the contrary furthers scientific study and results in a new perspective, opening new fields leading to hitherto unexplored data. By comparing the divisions of judgments furnished by Welton & Monahan, Stebbing, De Vleeschauwer and Vollenhoven, the conclusion is reached that the point of view presupposed by each division determines the criteria employed in the division of judgments; the view is taken that a Christian point of view constitutes an exceptionally liberal and balanced conception of the subject, and in various respects avoids one-sidedness, partiality and the limitations inherent in some other points of view. From this it is apparent that the consequences and implications of the point of view taken in the study of logic Chapter VI gives a short conclusionary view in which some important consequences of the previous expositions are enumerated and a few critical remarks added to illuminate some aspects of the problem. <1> Christian logic furnishes a particularly penetrating insight into the philosophical basis of logic. Philosophical matters influence in fundamental respects the scientific investigation of the logical field and it appears imperative that logic be based on a philosophical conception (from whatever point of view adopted). Logic is different from philosophy but the scientific activity in the field of logic nevertheless presupposes a philosophical standpoint, as Chapter II has indicated. Particularly important is the fact that Vollenhoven could demonstrate the necessity for the logician to keep in mind both the modality (viz. logical) and the character (viz. as result of a previous analytical activity) of the concept and judgment, as well as to investigate the retrocipations and anticipations of the logical function on sub- and superstratum spheres respectively; logic derives from philosophy the insight that all of this, and the analytical activity too, belong to the logical sphere. The conception developed in logic cannot be considered to be detached from more fundamental philosophical matters nor to be formal nor neutral. A Christian philosophy is especially necessary with a view to keeping the spheres of ontology and epistemology distinct, as well as to determine the difference between and the relationship of logic and on the one hand cosmology and anthropology, and on the other hand epistemology. A Christian logic reaps the advantages of this distinction. Besides the option of e.g. either rationalism or irrationalism, a Christian standpoint in scientific matters is practicable. The results of Dooyeweerd, Vollenhoven, Stoker, Van Til and others have changed the possibility of a Christian point of view in science (including logic) into a reality. Chapter IV especially has indicated that and how a Christian logic presupposes a Christian philosophy and in Chapter V it has been possible to point out the importance of a Christian approach to logic, even in its details. <2> As regards the matter investigated by logic and its character, the point of view is taken that logic is a science and that no scientist can•accept his task of investigation or execute his analysis without a determination of his field of study and the nature of this field, as well as testing the results obtained with this determination; moreover continued reflection is necessary as to whether the. investigation has succeeded in complying with the determination of the field of investigation. The supposition is held that the determination of the field of investigation is a distinction according to modality, that is to say logic has to investigate the analytical (logical) sphere of law. A Christian logic opposes the various forms of reduction-logic which screen the logical field down to some of the most obvious phenomena of the logical sphere. A Christian logic results in various new finds, as well as a new. perspective of the whole domain of logic. <3> Logic according to a Christian point of view is not what it is often thought to be and moreover it is different from the traditional conception. Logic as science is not formal nor neutral. A Christian point of view accepts the relevance of religion and considers the Word of God to be the guiding principle for directing scientific cognition in its scientific investigation of the logical field. Christian logic is no logic of religion or vice versa, no logical creed, logical science of belief or a logic of divine worship, nor a compilation of texts from the Holy Scriptures bearing on the logical function, etc. A Christian logic does not investigate the logical field from or v 1 a the function of belief. have effects even in the most particular details of the field of logic. / Thesis (MA)--PU vir CHO, 1959.
276

F.R. Leavis : a study in bourgeois criticism

Prakash, Chandra, 1940- January 1969 (has links)
No description available.
277

Op weg na 'n christelike logika : 'n studie van enkele vraagstukke in die logika met besondere aandag aan D.H.Th. Vollenhoven se visie van 'n christelike logika / Nicolaas Theodor van der Merwe

Van der Merwe, Nicolaas Theodor January 1958 (has links)
This study furnishes some results of an investigation to ascertain whether the possibility of a Christian logic can be maintained as a meaningful question. This problem seems to be enmeshed in a complex encompassing the problem of Christian science* as such. Whether the possibility of a Christian logic is maintained or denied, at any rate this implies a positive standpoint towards the problem of a Christian logic. Some general remarks having been made in an introductory chapter, the main aspects bearing on the background of different points of view towards logic are presented in Chapter II. <1> The general philosophical conception adopted seems to be of importance with a view to the formation of a conception of logic in at least and especially two respects. <a> Philosophical trends have a marked influence on the view taken of logic. As far as modern philosophy is concerned, one can point to the differences appertaining to logic, its character, and the domain accorded to logic as science, its place in the cosmic reality, etc., differences which become evident in the conceptions of, for example, Descartes, Arnauld & Nicole, Kant, Opzoomer, Heymans, Bolland, Dewey, Bergson and Heidegger. Whereas Dewey, Bergson and Heidegger move in an irrationalistic direction, the first mentioned six philosophers bear evidence of a rationalistic point of view. The idealistic conception of Kant differs from the scientialism of a Descartes and the practicalism of the writers of The Port Ro*al Logic; the difference can be traced to the fact that Kant lends .the divergent solutions furnished by scientialism and practicalism to a unity, which ascribes to the ~ human perceptive faculty two functions, a theoretical and practical; theoretical reason and practical reason are autonomous, each in its particular sphere. The more recent rationalism of an Opzoomer, Heymans and Bolland, keeps to the rationalistic main lines but takes the a priori's of autonomous reason in a dynamic-active sense by laying stress on the scientific methods. Positivism advanced the first solution in this direction, overestimating scientific theory in a scientialistic spirit, with the result that the practical existence is viewed in the light of science. The positivism of a Comte and Opzoomer finds an antipode in the neo-positivism of, for instance, Dilthey, Wundt and Heymans, laying stress on the practical aspect. And then the neoidealism of Cassirer, Bosanquet, Bolland and others bridges the opposition between the positivistic and nee-positivistic conceptions. The far-reaching influence of rationalistic conceptions encountered a serious set-back on account of the increasing importance attached to the se-called critique of science and especially the rise of irrationalistic conceptions. Irrationalism accepts reason in a rationalistic sense, but limits its validity and importance to a specific sphere. The pragQatism of James and Dewey, for instance, supports science only in so far as it furthers practical purposes: one has to obey reason in order to experiment, but the important point is exactly the fact that one is busy experimenting on account of a need bearing on practical life. A second trend, the "philosophy of life" which had an eminent exponent in Bergson, emphasizes the importance of "life" (taken in an organicpsychovitalistic sense) instead of practical utility, and therefore accentuates intuition in contrast to the symbolic operational method of intelligence (which "belong to the domain of logic). And finally existentialistically-minded philosophers champion the cause of human existence, of the individual concrete situation. It is pointed out that these differences in philosophical conception result in different points of view taken of logic. <b> Secondly the specific type of philosophical point of view is an ontological factor of supreme importance in the realisation of a conception of logic. Kant and Hegel, for instance, both advance an idealistic conception, but differ as to the type of philosophical point of view; for Hegel attaches himself to a contradictory type whereas Kant propounds an "ennoetic" conception which regards the sensations as furnishing the material for the forms of the intellect, that is to say, the intellect has the sensations as contents of the mind. Moreover I may refer to the interaction-theory of a Descartes and the instrumentistic point of view of a Bergson or the psychomonistic type represented by a Heymans, etc. Each particular type of philosophical conception involves a specific cosmology and anthropology, and results in a particular conception of logic and the problems of this branch of science. <2> In addition to the above mentioned ontological matters, it is necessary to point separately to the importance of epistemological factors for one's conception of logic. This point is illustrated by enumerating some basic problems of a theory of knowledge and explaining a few points in greater detail, for instance, <a> the possibility and suppositions of knowledge; <b> the analysis of knowledge (including the essence, character and kinds of knowledge), the formation of knowledge, the purpose of knowledge and the unity of knowledge (including limits and scope of knowledge, the partial nature and coherence of knowledge); and <c> the validity of knowledge (including knowledge and law, knowledge and value, as well as the reliability of knowledge). <3> In yet another respect different points of view may arise, viz. according to the opinion held as to logic as science, its character and domain, and the investigation of the logical field. There is, for instance, a trend in logic which attempts to approach the field of logic from that of mathematics, and on the other hand some logicians undertake the task of studying the basic principles of mathematics with logic as the starting-point. Moreover, also the points of view of psychologism in logic (Sigwart) and Husserl’s reaction against this trend, tend to show that the scientific determination of the field of investigation bears testimony to the fact that the logician cannot afford to neglect matters which can be traced to <a> different attitudes in theory of science, and <b > different points of view in regard to the field of investigation. <4> Lastly the suggestion may be offered that one-sided stressing of one or more of the different factors of importance (mentioned above) as such, may also result in different conceptions of logic. * * * Up to this point no attention has been paid to the possibility of the Christian conviction, the Christian "life and world-view", etc., as an important factor in the formation of a conception of logic. Chapter III gives a general survey of the points of view taken on logic in a Christian atmosphere. <1> A Christian logic is an utter impossibility; this is the first standpoint taken as to this problem. This, point of view comprises, however, various subordinate solutions of the problem. <a> Some argue that as far as the importance and implications of Christianity are concerned, Christianity is confined to divine worship and this does not bear on logic in any way whatsoever. <b> Others acknowledge the importance of Christianity for divine worship, and add: for daily practical life too --- although in no wise for science and therefore not for logic. <c> A third solution accepts the significance of Christianity for a section of science, for instance <i> as far as theology is concerned, <ii> and also for philosophy, <iii> and perhaps in some respects for other branches of science (e.g. sociology, ethnology, the science of history, etc.) but at any rate not as far as logic is concerned. <2> On the other hand some scientists, inspired by the reformational concept of Calvin, maintain that Christianity, that the Christian view of cosmos and man, the Christian approach to scientific matters, etc., must be esteemed a factor of importance so far as the conception of science as such is concerned, and that moreover it is imperative that all scientific investigations be undertaken in the light of the revelation (in Holy Scripture); for this reason among others the idea of a Christian logic is not absurd. This thesis can be elucidated by mentioning some contributions to a Christian logic, for instance, <a> A. Kuyper's opinion that science is of two kinds because humanity is of two kinds, those regarding the cosmos as normal and those who take into account the reality of the fall of man in Adam, and therefore acknowledge the fact that an act of interference on the part of God is necessary to put the cosmos again in a correct relation to Him. On account of this difference Kuyper therefore maintains the existence of a Christian and non Christian science. As the fact of sin dit not affect the formal activity of thinking, according to Kuyper, he states that the palingenesis does not cause any difference in this respect; therefore only one kind of logic exists --- a Christian logic. <b> S.O. Los indicates the necessity of a Christian logic by stating that the Calvinistic principles ought to find application in every section of science, not excluding logic. A Christian logic takes into account the principles of Holy Scripture and brings them to bear upon scientific studies. <c> H.G. Stoker's conception of the cosmos as a created coherent diversity implies i n t era 1 i a that the field of logic has an irreducible, unique character of its own, but the logical sphere is part of a comprehensive totality in which all diversity is given in a coherent complex. Because it is a radical diversity, it is unlike the psychical, lingual or ethical sphere, and therefore the logical sphere may not be reduced to any other diversity nor isolated from the diversity with which it constitutes a totality. On account of the fact that cosmic reality is a created diversity, it is not autonomous nor self-sufficient; a Christian logic therefore naturally opposes the dogma of the autonomy of thought.<d> C. Van Til points out that whereas the facts and laws with which logic is concerned, are not detached from their being created, the facts and laws of logic too are not self-sufficient, but part of created reality; accordingly it is imperative that the Christian truths (of, for instance, creation, fall of man into sin, and redemption in Jesus Christ in the communion of the Holy Spirit) be acknowledged from the very beginning. Indeed, as Van Til explains in detail, no part of Christianity remains intact when once the Arminian logic is allowed to run its course. <e> K. Schilder puts forward various considerations bearing on the impossibility of a formal or neutral logic, and states that logic has a foundation in fundamental philosophical ideas, on account of which a Hegelian, Fiahtian and Calvinist have different conceptions of logic; moreover, logic is not detached from other sciences, and in no science can one find one's way without a standpoint in faith. <f> H. Dooyeweerd's "philosophy of the cosmonomic idea" states and illustrates in various respects both the possibility and necessity of a Christian logic. Especially his theory of the nodal spheres each subjected to its own law, discloses an insight of great depth concerning the logical sphere as a modal aspect of cosmic reality, having the numerical and spatial aspects, the aspect of mathematical movement, the aspect of physical energy, of organic life and of psychical feeling as substratum spheres and the historical and linguistic aspects, the aspect of social intercourse, the economic, the aesthetic, the jural, the moral aspects and the aspect of faith as superstratum spheres. In its modal nucleus each sphere enjoys a sovereignty in its own sphere and differs from every other modal aspect; on account of retrocipations each sphere coheres with every previous sphere in the cosmic order and by means of anticipations with the superstratum spheres, thus presenting also a universality in its own sphere. The variable phenomena of each sphere function subjected to a law of their own, for instance, in the logical sphere judgements are subjected to the logical (analytical) law; accordingly this subject is treated as the theory of the spheres of law --- a really important milestone on the way towards a Christian logic, particularly so, as it has proved to be exceptionally useful in determining the characteristic nature of the logical sphere. <g> D.H.Th. Vollenhoven has established the cardinal data of a Christian logic and acquired an insight into such various points of importance for the problem of a Christian logic, that it is considered necessary to treat thereof in a separate chapter. * * * The first section of chapter IV is given to a general survey of the more important writings of Vollenhoven in so far as they contributed towards his conception of a Christian logic. An attempt is made to show how Vollenhoven arrived at his final conception. This section is also intended to furnish the basis for an interpretation of his conception, which follows in the succeeding parts of chapter IV. <1 > <a> Ontology presents an insight into the difference in the being of God, law and cosmos. God is the Sovereign who created the cosmos and put his law to the cosmos. Only God is sovereign, i.e. not subjected to the law. It is only of the law that one can say that it obtains (for that which is subjected to the law); and the being of the cosmos exists in its being subjected to. the law. <b > The word "law" can be taken in three different senses: as structural (modal) law, as the commandment of love, and as positive law. <c> The being of the cosmos displays a diversity of created subjects, heavenly and earthly. <d> By temporarily disregarding the essentials in which man differs from other "things", it is possible to investigate the being of the thing. It is necessary to distinguish the being of the subject and the object, both being subjected to the law, but in different respects. Both have to be investigated as to the modal (universal) differences and to the individual differences, as well as their particular relations and the bonds between modal differences (retrocipations and anticipations) and between individual differences (coherences). An object is a complex having a subject as the bearer of object-functions, attributes such as colour, warmth, etc.; although being more complex than the subject, subject and object have this in common that they are both subjected to the law. <e> The structure of man is even more complex. Beside modal differences and individual differences (having this specific individual characteristic and not that, on account of which this judgement differs from that judgment --- although they do-not differ modally as both are logical), the difference in direction of his functions (good or bad) is of extreme importance as far as the being of man is concerned. For the different modal functions constitute the frame for the activities of man, and therefore the logical sphere is called the logical function. The activities of the heart of man (prefunctional) are, as it were, sent into a specific functional channel; and this activity is directed by the heart in a twofold exit, namely for better or worse. <f> The structure of the realms (man, animal, plant and mineral) brings us to the genetic bond; and <g> as to the structure of mankind two points are worth mentioning, viz. <i> the bonds of community (their character, diversity and mutual relation) and <ii> religion as the covenant between God, the Creator of heaven and earth, and man. <h > After the particular relation between heaven and earth has been treated, the bond between God, law and cosmos demands attention. <2> Theory of knowledge is distinct from ontology but nevertheless presupposes a close relation. <a> The theory of human knowledge is discussed in two main sections: <i> the structure of the non-scientific cognition (including its suppositions; the knowable; the activity of learning-to-know; the result of knowing; and the bond between the result of knowing and the activity of learning, the knowable, and the norm of learning-to-know! and secondly the development of the non-scientific cognition), and <ii> the structure of the scientific cognition (including firstly the cognition in particular scientists method and the diversity of scientific methods in particular science, the analysable for particular sciences, and the result of scientific cognition in particular sciences; and secondly the scientific cognition of nonparticular sciences as, for instance, philosophy); <b> the theory of science investigates particular sciences• and non-particular sciences; and c > methodology studies the problem of method as such, as well as in relation to the different sciences, not excluding logic. <3> Under logic is discussed <a> fundamental philosophical questions, including those of <i> philosophy of the logical field which discloses an insight into the logical sphere of law --- which logic has to investigate --( including in particular the question of what the logical modality is and how the logical aspect is present in that which subsists gnostically),and <ii> philosophy of logic (including, the problem of logic as a science and that of its relation to philosophy). <b> Under the general structure of the analytical (logical) sphere attention is paid to <i> the analytical law and <ii> the analytically subjected, viz. the analytical subjects (including the analytical activity, and the result of this activity: concept and judgment) and the analytical objects (i.e. the• analytical aspect of all the sub analytical); furthermore the bond between analytical subject and object, and lastly the bond between the analytical law and the analytically subjected, as well as the bond between God, analytical law and the analytically subjected. Under the concept is discussed the concept as such, the division of concepts and the particular relations of concepts. The theory of judgment likewise avails itself of these three themes for treating judgment. Chapter V investigates some problems of a more particular nature in the domain of logic; the investigation has had to be restricted to three subjects. <1> The analytical (logical) law. <a> Firstly the question is considered whether an analytical law exists, and it is pointed out that logicians who do give attention to this question usually stress one-sidedly the importance of either the analysable or the analytical activity or the result of thinking (the thought). <b > As far as the sense of the analytical law is concerned, a point of particular importance is Vollenhoven's insight that the analytical law is <i> specifically an analytical (and no nonanalytical, e.g. a mathematical) law, <ii> a structural law, 1. e. a modal law, and <iii> as law, the boundary between God and cosmos. <c> As to the contents of the analytical law, some critical remarks are made about the conception of e.g. Welton &Monahan, and reference is made to the importance and consequences of Vollenhoven's synopsis of the contents of the analytical law: "analyse well the analysable, whatever it may be". <d> The discussion of the question whether the analytical law can or must be considered as being formal, touches a few facets of the problem and gives some arguments for the supposition that it is not formal. <e> Ontology (stating the fundamental distinction between the being of God, law and cosmos) appears of cardinal importance also in respect to the question whether the analytical law be .considered a norm. <f> Finally attention is drawn to fallacies, And the supposition is advanced that one's conception of the analytical law determines in important respects one's view held as to fallacies. Fallacies seem to be due chiefly to the following three causes: <i> by disobeying the analytical norm, <ii > by reason of the fact that the substratum-functions of the logical function fail and <iii> on account of "wickedness of heart". <2> With reference to R. Robinson some points of importance concerning the problem of definition are discussed. The attitude is taken that definition is a specific kind of judgment, viz. a judgment in which the predicate does not analyse or evaluate the subject of the judgment, but delimits the sphere and scope of the subject, determines it, defines it, that is to say: attributes a predicate to the subject of a judgment with a scientific purpose. Definition can be given of concepts, or words, or the contents of words or of concepts, or the meaning of words. Especially important is the fact that the theory about definition presupposes a specific category theory; accordingly a Christian standpoint adopted in scientific study results in a different point of view taken towards definition. Lastly may be mentioned. that the difference between scientific and non-scientific definition ought not be neglected. <3> The comprehensive problem of the division of judgments likewise indicates that a Christian standpoint in science (logic) does not impede or hamper the investigation of the field of logic --- in this case the division of judgments ---- but on the contrary furthers scientific study and results in a new perspective, opening new fields leading to hitherto unexplored data. By comparing the divisions of judgments furnished by Welton & Monahan, Stebbing, De Vleeschauwer and Vollenhoven, the conclusion is reached that the point of view presupposed by each division determines the criteria employed in the division of judgments; the view is taken that a Christian point of view constitutes an exceptionally liberal and balanced conception of the subject, and in various respects avoids one-sidedness, partiality and the limitations inherent in some other points of view. From this it is apparent that the consequences and implications of the point of view taken in the study of logic Chapter VI gives a short conclusionary view in which some important consequences of the previous expositions are enumerated and a few critical remarks added to illuminate some aspects of the problem. <1> Christian logic furnishes a particularly penetrating insight into the philosophical basis of logic. Philosophical matters influence in fundamental respects the scientific investigation of the logical field and it appears imperative that logic be based on a philosophical conception (from whatever point of view adopted). Logic is different from philosophy but the scientific activity in the field of logic nevertheless presupposes a philosophical standpoint, as Chapter II has indicated. Particularly important is the fact that Vollenhoven could demonstrate the necessity for the logician to keep in mind both the modality (viz. logical) and the character (viz. as result of a previous analytical activity) of the concept and judgment, as well as to investigate the retrocipations and anticipations of the logical function on sub- and superstratum spheres respectively; logic derives from philosophy the insight that all of this, and the analytical activity too, belong to the logical sphere. The conception developed in logic cannot be considered to be detached from more fundamental philosophical matters nor to be formal nor neutral. A Christian philosophy is especially necessary with a view to keeping the spheres of ontology and epistemology distinct, as well as to determine the difference between and the relationship of logic and on the one hand cosmology and anthropology, and on the other hand epistemology. A Christian logic reaps the advantages of this distinction. Besides the option of e.g. either rationalism or irrationalism, a Christian standpoint in scientific matters is practicable. The results of Dooyeweerd, Vollenhoven, Stoker, Van Til and others have changed the possibility of a Christian point of view in science (including logic) into a reality. Chapter IV especially has indicated that and how a Christian logic presupposes a Christian philosophy and in Chapter V it has been possible to point out the importance of a Christian approach to logic, even in its details. <2> As regards the matter investigated by logic and its character, the point of view is taken that logic is a science and that no scientist can•accept his task of investigation or execute his analysis without a determination of his field of study and the nature of this field, as well as testing the results obtained with this determination; moreover continued reflection is necessary as to whether the. investigation has succeeded in complying with the determination of the field of investigation. The supposition is held that the determination of the field of investigation is a distinction according to modality, that is to say logic has to investigate the analytical (logical) sphere of law. A Christian logic opposes the various forms of reduction-logic which screen the logical field down to some of the most obvious phenomena of the logical sphere. A Christian logic results in various new finds, as well as a new. perspective of the whole domain of logic. <3> Logic according to a Christian point of view is not what it is often thought to be and moreover it is different from the traditional conception. Logic as science is not formal nor neutral. A Christian point of view accepts the relevance of religion and considers the Word of God to be the guiding principle for directing scientific cognition in its scientific investigation of the logical field. Christian logic is no logic of religion or vice versa, no logical creed, logical science of belief or a logic of divine worship, nor a compilation of texts from the Holy Scriptures bearing on the logical function, etc. A Christian logic does not investigate the logical field from or v 1 a the function of belief. have effects even in the most particular details of the field of logic. / Thesis (MA)--PU vir CHO, 1959.
278

An evaluation of the development of rural enterprises in China since 1978.

Li, Jingjing January 2005 (has links)
The central government has attached great importance to the development of rural enterprises in China. As a result, rural enterprises have developed rapidly and become an important part of the national economy. The primary aim of this study was to examine how public policy has influenced the development of rural enterprises. The changes in public policy since 1978 did play a positive role in developing rural enterprises. These positive roles have been manifested in the ideological base of policy, financial and tax policies, improving management and technological strategy.
279

Finite projective planes and related combinatorial systems / David G. Glynn.

Glynn, David Gerald January 1978 (has links)
Includes bibliography. / 281 p ; 30 cm. / Title page, contents and abstract only. The complete thesis in print form is available from the University Library. / Thesis (Ph.D.)--Dept. of Pure Mathematics, University of Adelaide, 1978
280

Les Francophones du Nouveau-Brunswick /

Vernex, Jean-Claude. January 1978 (has links)
Thèse--Lettres--Lyon II, 1975. / Bibliogr. t. 2, p. 79-127. Index.

Page generated in 0.0293 seconds