• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 37
  • 8
  • 5
  • 3
  • 3
  • 2
  • 2
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • 1
  • Tagged with
  • 74
  • 61
  • 32
  • 25
  • 17
  • 12
  • 11
  • 9
  • 9
  • 8
  • 8
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • 7
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
21

Contingency, truth, and tradition Alasdair MacIntyre's and Richard Rorty's view of narrative /

Barthold, Lauren Swayne, January 1993 (has links)
Thesis (M.C.S.)--Regent College, Vancouver, BC, 1993. / Abstract and vita. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 146-150).
22

The failure of the enlightenment ethical project according to Alasdair MacIntyre

Glodek, Jaroslaw. January 1995 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. L.)--Catholic University of America, 1995. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 67-69).
23

Contingency, truth, and tradition Alasdair MacIntyre's and Richard Rorty's view of narrative /

Barthold, Lauren Swayne, January 1993 (has links) (PDF)
Thesis (M.C.S.)--Regent College, Vancouver, BC, 1993. / Abstract and vita. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 146-150).
24

Sharpening Albert Borgmann's notion of "focal things and practices" through the insights of Alasdair MacIntyre's moral philosophy

Bjorgan, Jeffrey C. D. January 2005 (has links)
Thesis (M.C.S.)--Regent College, 2005. / Abstract and vita. Includes bibliographical references (leaves [80]-87).
25

Contingency, truth, and tradition Alasdair MacIntyre's and Richard Rorty's view of narrative /

Barthold, Lauren Swayne, January 1993 (has links)
Thesis (M.C.S.)--Regent College, Vancouver, BC, 1993. / Abstract and vita. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 146-150).
26

Sharpening Albert Borgmann's notion of "focal things and practices" through the insights of Alasdair MacIntyre's moral philosophy

Bjorgan, Jeffrey C. D. January 2005 (has links)
Thesis (M.C.S.)--Regent College, 2005. / Abstract and vita. Includes bibliographical references (leaves [80]-87).
27

MacIntyre, virtue, and liberalism response to Schneewind /

Wright, David E. January 2008 (has links)
Thesis (M.A.)--Ohio University, November, 2008. / Title from PDF t.p. Includes bibliographical references.
28

As virtudes da responsabilidade compartilhada: uma ampliação da teoria das virtudes de Alasdair MacIntyre

Sousa, José Elielton de January 2016 (has links)
Made available in DSpace on 2016-05-04T12:04:38Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 000478334-Texto+Parcial-0.pdf: 351200 bytes, checksum: cc9c9a1afd85e7438433029b967c21c1 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2016 / The thesis is an effort to expand Alasdair MacIntyre’s theory of virtues by adding a third set of virtues, namely, the virtues of shared responsibility. Therefore, we set out to explain the historical, plural, and unfinished character of his conception of virtue, by means of the intertwining of the concepts of practices, narrative order of a single human life, and tradition. Then, considering the weakness and dependence of the human animal, we demonstrate the naturalistic and open aspects of the concept of the human good that underpin the transition from animality to rationality, analyzing the concepts of animal human identity, practical rationality, and flourishing. Finally, in order to recognize the limits of MacIntyre’s virtue theory regarding the implications of human vulnerability and dependence resulting from its animal condition, we propose the addition of a third set of virtues to MacIntyre’s typology, namely, the virtues of shared responsibility. / A tese consiste num esforço para ampliar a teoria das virtudes de Alasdair MacIntyre, através da adição de um terceiro conjunto de virtudes – as virtudes da responsabilidade compartilhada. Para tanto, primeiramente explicitaremos o caráter histórico, plural e inacabado de seu conceito de virtudes, através do entrelaçamento dos conceitos de prática, ordem narrativa de uma vida humana singular e tradição. Em seguida, considerando a fragilidade e dependência do animal humano, demonstramos o aspecto naturalista e aberto do conceito de bem humano que fundamenta o processo de transição da animalidade para a racionalidade, analisando os conceitos de identidade humana animal, racionalidade prática e florescimento. Por fim, ao reconhecermos os limites da teoria das virtudes de MacIntyre quanto às implicações da vulnerabilidade e dependência humana decorrente de sua condição animal, proporemos o acréscimo de um terceiro conjunto de virtudes à tipologia macintyriana: as virtudes da responsabilidade compartilhada.
29

From Meaningful Work to Good Work: Reexamining the Moral Foundation of the Calling Orientation

Potts, Garrett W. 29 June 2019 (has links)
The calling orientation to work represents the seed that has germinated into the exponentially growing ‘work as a calling’ literature. It was first articulated by Robert Bellah, Richard Madsen, William Sullivan, Ann Swidler, and Steven Tipton within Habits of the Heart in the 1980s. The following critical analysis of the ‘work as a calling’ literature, and of the moral foundation of the calling orientation more specifically, is intended for two particular audiences. The first audience broadly includes an interdisciplinary group of scholars working within business ethics, management, organizational psychology, and vocational psychology, among other fields of study. Amidst these scholars’ exponentially increasing interest in the idea of ‘work as a calling,’ the anatomical structure of their research remains remarkably similar. Their notions of ‘work as a calling’ stress that work should provide individuals with a deep sense of personal fulfillment. In particular, they suggest that work should be a therapeutic source of individual meaning. To secure this meaning, they exhibit an apparent centeredness on the self and an emphasis on the unconstrained pursuit of personal preferences. In most cases, scholars within the ‘work as a calling’ literature tend to proffer notions of ‘meaningful work’ that are divorced from moral considerations about ‘good work.’ While this broad group of scholars copiously references the calling orientation within their research on ‘work as a calling,’ a deep-seated misunderstanding pervades the literature to the extent that notions of ‘meaningful work’ have been divorced from notions of ‘good work.’ To this broader audience, I demonstrate herein that they do not realize how antithetical their scholarly literature on ‘work as a calling’ is to the moral foundation of Bellah et al.’s calling orientation. Namely, I argue that the construal of calling as an orientation to work would not exist within the literature if Bellah et al. had not first articulated the calling orientation as a buffer against the unregulated pursuit of personal preferences. Therefore, I claim that this broader group of scholars either needs to abandon the notion of ‘work as a calling’ or engage with the appropriate virtue framework that undergirds the calling orientation. I suspect, however, that several of these scholars will be hesitant to take up the virtue framework that is inextricably linked to the calling orientation. For this reason, much of the work following chapter 2 is devoted to a narrower audience of MacIntyrean business ethicists. It is also dedicated to a few scholars from the broader ‘work as a calling’ group whom I trust will not wish to remain accidental contributors to the language of individualism that pervades the literature once I have unmasked it. Perhaps, in time, they will even become MacIntyrean business ethicists. Indeed, the appropriate moral framework that undergirds the ‘work as a calling’ literature is actively being worked out by a narrower group of MacIntyrean business ethicists, all of whom represent my primary audience for the research herein. To the MacIntyrean community, I hope not only to provide a complete list of tendencies within the ‘work as a calling’ literature that must be resisted, but also a picture of all of the ways that Bellah et al.’s calling orientation is wholly bound up with MacIntyre’s moral philosophy – particularly his theory of the virtues and the common goods that the virtues sustain. Bellah et al.’s calling orientation rests upon a vision of ‘good work,’ and this vision of ‘good work’ hinges on a MacIntyrean account of the virtues that is directed toward the achievement of three distinct types of common goods: (a) the good and worthy ends of workplace practices, (b) the goods of an individual life, and (c) the goods of communities – or, more broadly, the interests of a good society. Furthermore, it will be shown to the MacIntyrean community that visions of ‘good work,’ which are sustained by the calling orientation, are accompanied by a nuanced vision of pluralistic collaboration that MacIntyre and Bellah et al. share. (I anticipate that this will be surprising to many readers who are familiar with the typical and misleading characterization of MacIntyre as a sectarian). Bellah et al. as well as MacIntyre’s vision of pluralism matters for research on the calling orientation because these figures demonstrate that individuals within the late modern workplace are informed by a plurality of religious and humanistic traditions, all of which account for ultimate meaning and goodness in different ways that ought to be recognized. Distinctive religious and humanistic visions of ultimate meaning indeed impact the perceived goodness of one’s calling. Hence, we must attend to the polysemic and multivocal nature of accounting for the goodness of any one particular calling (i.e., a Buddhist doctor within the Western medical tradition is likely to articulate the goodness of his calling differently than a Jewish doctor working within the Western medical tradition). Still, however, Bellah et al. and MacIntyre’s account entails a hopefulness in the possibility of pluralistic, (or, what I shall call inter-traditional) striving for the achievement of common goods that are practical enough to agree upon.
30

Shades of Gray: The Peculiar Postmodernism of Alasdair Gray

Böhnke, Dietmar 18 October 2018 (has links)
No description available.

Page generated in 0.0275 seconds