31 |
Re-thinking the common law of defamation : striking a new balance between freedom of expression and the protection of the individual’s reputationBayer, Carolin Anne 11 1900 (has links)
Reputational interests are protected against defamatory and injurious statements by the common
law o f defamation, which permits the targeted individual to recover damages for the injury to his
reputation. At the same time, this body of common law sets limits to the constitutional right to
free expression of the person who made the penalized communication. However, since s.32(l)
of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms - according to the Supreme Court of Canada -
restricts the Charter's application to the actions of legislative, executive and administrative
branches of government, the Charter will be at best a bit player in defamation litigation
governed by common law rule.
This thesis deals with the tension between promoting free speech and protecting a person's
reputation, i.e. with the questions whether the common law of defamation has achieved the
correct balance between the protection of the individual's reputation and freedom of expression,
or whether it needs to be modified in order to better accord with the Charter.
A n important component of this thesis is its review of the decision of Hill v. Church of
Scientology, where the Supreme Court of Canada addressed the question of whether defamation
law needs to be reconsidered in light o f the Charter protection of free expression, and found the
balance struck by the current law to be appropriate. A critical look at this decision, and more
generally at the law of defamation itself, particularly its presumptions of falsity, malice and
damages, will reveal the problems with the common law's resistance to making any major
allowance for free expression.
The author will argue that the Charter should apply to the common law in the same way as it
applies to statutory law and that defamation law in particular would, in all probability, not
survive the test under s.l of the Charter, concerning the justification of a limitation to a
fundamental right. It will be concluded that the common law of defamation needs to be
modified, i.e. that it must accord significantly more weight to freedom of expression in order to
be consistent with the Charter.
Insofar as the extent of such modification is concerned, the author will propose first of all to
give the element of fault a more significant role in the common law of defamation. In addition,
she will argue that the common law presumptions should be abolished. In sum, the author's
reform proposal requires the plaintiff to prove not only that the words he complains of are
defamatory, identify him and are published to a third person, but also that they are false, did
indeed cause damage to his reputation and that the defendant acted with fault, i.e. intentionally
or negligently, when publishing the defamatory falsehoods. / Law, Peter A. Allard School of / Graduate
|
32 |
The charter and election law in Canada : towards a unified theory of judicial review?Letkeman, Emily Susan 11 1900 (has links)
The advent of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms signaled a new and vastly
expanded role for the judiciary. By entrenching our civil liberties into the Canadian
Constitution, the courts were given the express authority to override inconsistent statutes.
Due to the inherent overlap between law and politics, election law is an area that is
particularly sensitive to this recent enlargement of judicial power. Despite this, the courts
have scrutinized many areas of election law and many federal and provincial statutes
have been fundamentally altered. The purpose of this thesis is to determine whether the
courts have developed a uniform theory of judicial review where election law is
concerned via four case studies: electoral boundary redistribution, prisoner voting rights,
the publication of opinion polls during campaigns and third party spending limits.
Through an extensive review of the relevant case law and literature, I conclude that the
courts have failed to develop a coherent and consistent theory judicial review regarding
the application of the Charter to election law. My analysis reveals that the inconsistencies
stem largely from three main sources: first is the failure of the courts to adopt a single
vision of what constitutes a fair electoral system; second is that the case studies are
dealing with two different sections of the Charter (ss. 2(b) and 3); and third is the Oakes
test which has expanded judicial discretion along with the potential for disparity. If
consistency is ever going to be achieved, the courts need to adopt a single vision of
democracy in Canada. Until then, we are left to guess when our political rights may be
justifiably restricted under the Charter. / Arts, Faculty of / Political Science, Department of / Graduate
|
33 |
Social rights : the implications of selective constitutionalisationDaly, Gillian 11 1900 (has links)
This thesis is concerned with those 'social' rights that relate to the provision of the
basic necessities of life; that is the right to an adequate standard of living (including
food, clothing and shelter), the right to health and the right to education. The
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural rights (ICESCR) recognises
obligations pertaining to the progressive realisation of these rights, whilst leaving the
method of implementation within domestic discretion.
The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms only accords domestic constitutional
protection to civil rights, leaving the implementation of these social rights within
government discretion. This study will examine what has, in the Canadian experience,
proven to be the practical consequences of adopting such a policy of 'selective
constitutionalisation,' that puts social rights by definition outside the ambit of legal
enforcement.
Firstly, it will examine the court's approach to cases that have, in the absence of
constitutionalised social rights, attempted to indirectly invoke social rights by
encouraging a positive social interpretation of the right to equality and the right to life,
liberty and security of the person, and will illustrate that the courts have failed to
interpret these rights so as to indirectly protect social rights.
Secondly, it will consider the relationship between legal, political and social
discourse, illustrating that, in light of the non- constitutionalised status of social
rights, the values underlying these rights have been marginalised in political and
social discourse, facilitating reforms that have restructured and eroded the welfare
state, reducing the realisation of social rights within Canada.
Thirdly, it will consider the practicability of adopting the alternative approach of
according equal constitutional protection and justiciable status to social rights,
through an examination of the theoretical literature and the approach taken to social
rights under the Final Constitution of the Republic of South Africa 1996. It will
illustrate that the philosophical arguments that have been utilised to support the nonconstitutionalised
status of social rights are no longer sustainable and that the
constitutional experience of South Africa provides evidence that a practical alternative
to the position adopted in Canada exists. / Law, Peter A. Allard School of / Graduate
|
34 |
The political impact of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms on the Supreme Court of Canada /Romano, Domenic January 1989 (has links)
No description available.
|
35 |
The role of the courts in the evolution of Canadian constitutionalism : historical antecedents and future prospectsCrossland, James January 1987 (has links)
No description available.
|
36 |
Les valeurs afférentes à la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés dans le discours judiciaire : utilisations et sourcesBousquet, Guillaume 10 1900 (has links)
Mémoire numérisé par la Division de la gestion de documents et des archives de l'Université de Montréal. / Dans les décisions où entre en jeu la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés, les
juges construisent leurs raisonnements à partir des droits et libertés énumérés dans son
libellé, mais également à partir de valeurs. Parmi ces valeurs afférentes à la Charte se
retrouvent notamment la protection des groupes vulnérables, la protection de la vie
privée et de la réputation de la personne, le respect de la dignité inhérente de l'être
humain, la promotion de la justice et de l'égalité sociale de même que l'encouragement à
l'épanouissement personnel. Contrairement aux droits et libertés, lesquels furent
directement inscrits par le constituant dans le libellé de la Charte, les valeurs représentent
une création de l'appareil judiciaire.
Malgré la composante subjective que l'on attribue généralement aux valeurs, nous
constatons que la sécurité du droit ne se trouve pas fragilisée par l'incorporation d'une
dimension axiologique dans le raisonnement judiciaire en matière de Charte. Au
contraire, le recours aux valeurs favorise la constance et la prévisibilité dans l'application
et l'interprétation de cet instrument de protection des droits et libertés.
D'une part, les valeurs afférentes à la Charte sont utilisées de façon rigoureuse
dans le contrôle judiciaire de la constitutionnalité des lois, dans l'adaptation des règles de
common law et dans l'interprétation des lois. Les juges invoquent fréquemment les
mêmes valeurs, à quelques variantes près, assurant ainsi une certaine stabilité dans le
traitement des composantes axiologiques de la Charte.
D'autre part, les juges sont largement capables de dissocier de leurs convictions
personnelles les valeurs qu'ils invoquent dans leurs décisions. Les valeurs tirées des
comportements sociaux actuels, du droit international et du droit comparé, de même que
des ouvrages des philosophes politiques et des théoriciens du droit, sont des valeurs qui
ont peu à voir avec les sentiments, les opinions ou les intérêts personnels des juges. / In cases involving the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, judges include
in their reasoning not only rights and freedoms, but also values. Among these Charter
values we find protection of vulnerable groups, respect for the inherent dignity of human
beings, cultivation oUndividual self-fulfillment and human flourishing, commitment to
social justice and protection of privacy rights and reputation. Contrary to rights and
freedoms, which are specifically enumerated in the Charter, values represent a creation of
the judicial apparatus.
Notwithstanding their inherent subjective component, values do not weaken the
law's predictability nor do they endanger judicial reasoning concerning the Charter. On
the contrary, applying values brings constancy and certainty in the interpretation of the
Charter.
On the one hand, Charter values are used in rigorous ways in the judicial review
of constitutionality, in the adaptation of common law mIes and in the interpretation of
laws and by-Iaws. Judges have recourse to more or less the same values, thus bringing
stability in the Charter's analysis.
On the other hand, judges are able to dissociate their personal beliefs from the
values they caU upon in their judgments. Values drawn from contemporary social
behaviors, international law and comparative law, as weU as political and legal
philosophers' works, are values quite distant from judges' feelings, opinions and
personal interests.
|
37 |
Charter activism and Canadian federalism : rebalancing liberal constitutionalism in Canada, 1982 to 1997Kelly, James B. January 1998 (has links)
The introduction of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms has affected many elements of the constitutional system in Canada. This dissertation explores the Charter's relationship with liberal constitutionalism and Canadian federalism, and considers whether judicial review on Charter grounds has seen a progression, or a regression, from parliamentary to constitutional to judicial supremacy. Further, this dissertation considers whether Charter review has reduced provincial autonomy by imposing national values in provincial areas of jurisdiction when Charter review nullifies provincial statutes. Through a complex process referred to as the rebalancing of liberal constitutionalism, this study argues that a changed Charter jurisprudence by the Supreme Court of Canada and a changed policy process within the administrative state at the federal level have reduced the negative implications of Charter review for liberal constitutionalism and Canadian federalism. To advance this argument, the concept of Charter activism is introduced to demonstrate that the rebalancing of liberal constitutionalism is the product of the shifting equilibrium within two distinct elements that comprise Charter activism---judicial activism and bureaucratic activism. This study pursues three themes to demonstrate that the decline of judicial activism and the emergence of bureaucratic activism now converge at a point within Charter politics that facilitate the rebalancing of liberal constitutionalism and ensure that Charter review advances constitutional and not judicial supremacy. The first theme investigates the Supreme Court of Canada as a policy actor during Charter review, and analyzes Charter decisions between 1982 and 1997. The second theme considers the impact of Charter review on Canadian federalism and whether the Charter has centralized Canadian federalism and reduced provincial autonomy. The final theme investigates bureaucratic activism and the changes within the policy process at the fe
|
38 |
Les valeurs afférentes à la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés dans le discours judiciaire : utilisations et sourcesBousquet, Guillaume 10 1900 (has links)
Dans les décisions où entre en jeu la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés, les
juges construisent leurs raisonnements à partir des droits et libertés énumérés dans son
libellé, mais également à partir de valeurs. Parmi ces valeurs afférentes à la Charte se
retrouvent notamment la protection des groupes vulnérables, la protection de la vie
privée et de la réputation de la personne, le respect de la dignité inhérente de l'être
humain, la promotion de la justice et de l'égalité sociale de même que l'encouragement à
l'épanouissement personnel. Contrairement aux droits et libertés, lesquels furent
directement inscrits par le constituant dans le libellé de la Charte, les valeurs représentent
une création de l'appareil judiciaire.
Malgré la composante subjective que l'on attribue généralement aux valeurs, nous
constatons que la sécurité du droit ne se trouve pas fragilisée par l'incorporation d'une
dimension axiologique dans le raisonnement judiciaire en matière de Charte. Au
contraire, le recours aux valeurs favorise la constance et la prévisibilité dans l'application
et l'interprétation de cet instrument de protection des droits et libertés.
D'une part, les valeurs afférentes à la Charte sont utilisées de façon rigoureuse
dans le contrôle judiciaire de la constitutionnalité des lois, dans l'adaptation des règles de
common law et dans l'interprétation des lois. Les juges invoquent fréquemment les
mêmes valeurs, à quelques variantes près, assurant ainsi une certaine stabilité dans le
traitement des composantes axiologiques de la Charte.
D'autre part, les juges sont largement capables de dissocier de leurs convictions
personnelles les valeurs qu'ils invoquent dans leurs décisions. Les valeurs tirées des
comportements sociaux actuels, du droit international et du droit comparé, de même que
des ouvrages des philosophes politiques et des théoriciens du droit, sont des valeurs qui
ont peu à voir avec les sentiments, les opinions ou les intérêts personnels des juges. / In cases involving the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, judges include
in their reasoning not only rights and freedoms, but also values. Among these Charter
values we find protection of vulnerable groups, respect for the inherent dignity of human
beings, cultivation oUndividual self-fulfillment and human flourishing, commitment to
social justice and protection of privacy rights and reputation. Contrary to rights and
freedoms, which are specifically enumerated in the Charter, values represent a creation of
the judicial apparatus.
Notwithstanding their inherent subjective component, values do not weaken the
law's predictability nor do they endanger judicial reasoning concerning the Charter. On
the contrary, applying values brings constancy and certainty in the interpretation of the
Charter.
On the one hand, Charter values are used in rigorous ways in the judicial review
of constitutionality, in the adaptation of common law mIes and in the interpretation of
laws and by-Iaws. Judges have recourse to more or less the same values, thus bringing
stability in the Charter's analysis.
On the other hand, judges are able to dissociate their personal beliefs from the
values they caU upon in their judgments. Values drawn from contemporary social
behaviors, international law and comparative law, as weU as political and legal
philosophers' works, are values quite distant from judges' feelings, opinions and
personal interests. / Mémoire numérisé par la Division de la gestion de documents et des archives de l'Université de Montréal
|
39 |
Charter activism and Canadian federalism : rebalancing liberal constitutionalism in Canada, 1982 to 1997Kelly, James B. January 1998 (has links)
No description available.
|
40 |
Beyond Umpire and Arbiter: Courts as Facilitators of Intergovernmental Dialogue in Division of Powers Cases in CanadaWright, Wade Kenneth January 2014 (has links)
The courts in Canada have often been cast, by both courts and legal scholars, as 'umpires' or 'arbiters' of the federal-provincial division of powers - umpires or arbiters that have the exclusive, or at least decisive, authority to clarify and enforce, and resolve disputes about, 'who does what' in the federal system. However, the image conveyed by these metaphors underestimates the role that the federal and provincial political branches play in the federal system, by working out their own solutions, in the intergovernmental arena, both directly and indirectly, where questions and disputes arise about how jurisdiction is and should be allocated. The image conveyed by the umpire or arbiter metaphors also sits uncomfortably with the facilitative role that the Supreme Court of Canada has carved out for itself in its recent division of powers decisions, a role that casts the courts as facilitators of these instances of intergovernmental dialogue.
This doctoral dissertation challenges, and moves beyond, the umpire and arbiter metaphors. It examines the political safeguards available to the provinces in Canada to prevent, or limit, perceived federal encroachments on provincial jurisdiction, in the process highlighting the role that the political branches play in Canada in working out their own allocations of jurisdiction, outside of the courts. It describes, and critically evaluates, the facilitative role carved out by the Court in its recent division of powers decisions, identifying various reasons to be skeptical of a facilitative role that casts the courts as facilitators of intergovernmental dialogue. Finally, and with an eye to future research, it briefly outlines an alternative facilitative role that focuses on facilitating deliberation about the division of powers implications of particular initiatives, arguing that it would be premature to dismiss facilitative approaches to judicial review altogether.
|
Page generated in 0.0954 seconds