Spelling suggestions: "subject:"ehe thought"" "subject:"hhe thought""
51 |
The Chinese religious spirit龔道運, Keong, Tow-yung. January 1965 (has links)
published_or_final_version / Chinese / Master / Master of Arts
|
52 |
A study of the effects of thought suppression techniquesLin, Yi-Jen 28 August 2008 (has links)
Not available / text
|
53 |
The rise and spread of Socinianism in England before 1689McLachlan, Herbert John January 1949 (has links)
No description available.
|
54 |
The history and value of the distinction between intellect and intuitionAaron, Richard Ithamar January 1926 (has links)
No description available.
|
55 |
The part played by kinaesthetic experience in perception and thinkingStrzałkowski, Wiesław January 1946 (has links)
No description available.
|
56 |
Digital-analogic thinking and its measurementDjap, Djam Dung. January 1979 (has links)
No description available.
|
57 |
Thought experiments in ethics : a contexualist approach to the grounding problemHarland, Anne 05 1900 (has links)
How can an experiment which occurs only in thought lead to new and accurate
conclusions about the world beyond thought? What makes thought experiments relevant
to the domains they are designed to explore?
One answer is that successful thought experiments are grounded. Explaining the
nature of this grounding relationship, especially as it applies to ethics, is the main task of
this dissertation.
A thought experiment is an experiment that occurs in thought. The "thought"
label distinguishes it from an ordinary physical experiment, while the "experiment" label
distinguishes it from other types of merely analogical, conjectural, or hypothetical
reasoning. Many of the components that are necessary for a successful physical
experiment are also necessary for a successful thought experiment. A thought
experiment, like a physical experiment, must isolate and vary variables in order to answer
a question within a given theoretical context. The result of the experiment has
repercussions for its theoretical context.
The grounding relationship holds between the components of the thought
experiment and the theoretical context of the thought experiment. In order for the
thought experiment to be successful, both the experimental set-up and our responses to it
need to be grounded in the thought experiment's theoretical context.
An experimental set-up will be grounded whenever it meets the following
conditions. The concepts used must be defined normally, dependent and independent
variables must be isolated and relevantly related, and the propositions of the thought
experiment (excepting those describing extraneous particulars) must be relevantly related
to the given theoretical context and the question under examination.
Grounding responses to thought experiments will then be largely a matter of
anticipating and disarming distorting influences. Factors influencing responses include
the individual's knowledge of the theoretical context, the state of development of that
context, the nature of the presentation of the thought experiment, and subjective filters.
It is sometimes difficult to ascertain whether a thought experiment in ethics is
grounded. This is largely due to the nature of the theoretical context of thought
experiments in ethics. In order to assess the relationship of thought experiments in ethics
to their theoretical context, I advocate employing a contextualist methodology involving
the process of wide reflective equilibrium. While contextualists use this approach to
arrive at considered judgements relating to specific ethical problems, I show that wide
reflective equilibrium can also be used to examine the grounding of thought experiments.
I conclude the dissertation with an examination of the relationship of thought
experiments to computer simulations, a study of various common thought experiment
distortions, and some tests and methods designed to aid constructing successful thought
experiments.
|
58 |
Returning To Our SensesBusuioc, Octavian Alexandru 27 September 2007 (has links)
The following thesis is concerned with the way we think of particular objects. More specifically, it is concerned with de re thoughts and beliefs, which are parasitic upon the objects they are about. In ascribing and expressing de re thoughts and beliefs, we employ de re expressions, such as demonstratives and names. There is a pervasive view in the philosophy of language, known as the direct-reference view, that claims that these expressions contribute to thoughts nothing over and above objects themselves. I argue that not only is this view of de re expressions untenable upon reflection on its repercussions for cognitive significance and judgement, but also that the considerations that motivate its genesis rest on a mistaken understanding of the alternative, viz a Fregean understanding of thought that employs a notion of sense. In the first chapter, I present logical difficulties that face accounts of de re belief and a quasi-Fregean response to them. In the second chapter, I focus on two exhaustive interpretations of the cognitive significance of de re expressions on the direct-reference view, and I argue that both interpretations are untenable either because they cannot account for propositional unity, or because they isolate experience from judgement. In the third chapter, I present a holistic interpretation of sense, and argue that it is neither faced by critiques presented by proponents of direct-reference, nor by the difficulties I articulate in the first two chapters. / Thesis (Master, Philosophy) -- Queen's University, 2007-09-21 10:53:33.232
|
59 |
The convergent-divergent abilities of students and their teachers /Zussman, David. January 1975 (has links)
No description available.
|
60 |
The cognitive analysis of flexible thinkingMay, J. January 1987 (has links)
No description available.
|
Page generated in 0.056 seconds