Spelling suggestions: "subject:"then presocratics"" "subject:"then presocratic""
1 |
Os princípios cosmológicos de Filolau e a músicaOliveira, Guilherme Magalhães 05 November 2010 (has links)
Made available in DSpace on 2016-04-27T17:26:52Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1
Guilherme Magalhaes Oliveira.pdf: 689794 bytes, checksum: 9f5057f96f879fa225b4f24f6f1b8b1e (MD5)
Previous issue date: 2010-11-05 / Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico / Our object of study is the relation between music and cosmology in Pythagoreanism,
specifically in the fragments by Philolaus of Croton (470-385 b.C.), a pythagorean
philosopher who influenced both Platonic and Aristotelian philosophy. This investigation is
divided into four parts: (1) Music in Ancient Greece, where we briefly examine the meaning
of the word mousike and its relation to Greek culture, from Homer up until the Lyrical Poets.
(2) Pythagoras and Pythagoreanism, where we discuss who was Pythagoras and his
community. (3) Philolaus Pythagoreanism, where we analyze Philolaus fragments and
explain the principles of his cosmology. Here, the meaning of limited (peras) and
unlimited (apeira), his two cosmological principles, are discussed. Then we investigate the
concept of harmony, understood here as a third principle, which serves the purpose of
uniting in good proportion the first two principles in order to form an ordered whole
(kosmos). As we look into the meaning of harmony, we also analyze the importance of the
number, or arithmos, in Philolaus philosophy, since it is directly related to the concept of
harmony. (4) In Music and the Cosmos, after we have explained Philolaus fundamental
concepts, we demonstrate how they are linked to music, i.e. to the numeric ratios that are
considered to be musical (or sound) intervals and the formation of the diatonic scale.
According to Philolaus and the Pythagoreans, this scale presents a specific
mathematical/musical structure, which is an image or imitation of the structure of the kosmos.
Finally, we show that Philolaus diatonic scale is also used by Plato, on his Timeu / Nosso objeto de estudo é a relação entre música e cosmologia no pitagorismo, mais
especificamente nos fragmentos de Filolau de Crotona (470-385 a.C.), filósofo pitagórico que
exerceu influência na filosofia platônica e aristotélica. Esta investigação está dividida em
quatro partes: (1) Música na Grécia Antiga, onde investigamos brevemente o significado da
palavra mousike e sua relação com a cultura grega de Homero até os Poetas Líricos. (2)
Pitágoras e o Pitagorismo, onde investigamos quem foi Pitágoras e sua comunidade. (3) O
Pitagorismo de Filolau, onde analisaremos os fragmentos de Filolau e explicaremos os
princípios de sua cosmologia. Será abordado o significado de limitado (peras) e ilimitado
(apeira), seus dois princípios cosmológicos. Em segundo lugar, investigaremos o significado
de harmonia, aqui entendida como um terceiro princípio, que possui o papel de unir em boa
proporção os dois primeiros princípios para formar um todo ordenado (kosmos). Ao
investigarmos o significado de harmonia, também apresentaremos a importância do número,
ou arithmos, na filosofia de Filolau, já que este está diretamente relacionado com a harmonia.
(4) A Música e o Cosmos, última parte de nosso trabalho que, após termos explicado os
conceitos fundamentais de Filolau, mostraremos como eles estão vinculados com a música, ou
seja, com as razões numéricas entendidas como intervalos musicais (de sons) e com a
formação da escala diatônica que, segundo Filolau e os pitagóricos, possui uma estrutura
matemático-musical específica, que é uma imagem ou imitação da estrutura do kosmos. Por
último, mostraremos que essa escala de Filolau é a mesma usada por Platão, no Timeu
|
2 |
Mythos e logos no poema de ParmênidesConte, Bruno Loureiro 04 November 2010 (has links)
Made available in DSpace on 2016-04-27T17:26:51Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1
Bruno Loureiro Conte.pdf: 597433 bytes, checksum: 474791994388813765e9eb9230745941 (MD5)
Previous issue date: 2010-11-04 / Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior / It is widely known that Parmenides Poem, which is considered a fundamental work in Greek
philosophical thought, presents a plurality of mythical elements, and that its clarification constitutes
an issue to the interpreters. This research is an investigation of the historical and
philosophical meaning of mythos and logos in the Poem, considering the work in its cultural
contexts. Our analysis begins by bringing to the foreground the presence of mythos, understood
in its original sense of authorized way of speaking, pointing out its interweaving with logos,
in such a manner that without the former the argument of the latter would remain incomprehensible.
On the other hand, we aim to determine the specificity of logos in Parmenides:
it shows up as a reflexive, refutative logos, but not, as some interpreters have sustained, a
strict demonstration . Having established this point, Parmenides work shows itself as productive
of a plurality of mythical assemblages, appropriating images of the traditional inspired
poet, of initiation in cults of mystery, of divinity figures and of the Archaic Lyric conception of
human existence. Furthermore, the Poem deploys itself in multiple discursive configurations:
narration, argument, oracular speaking. In accordance to that, we introduce an interpretative
hypothesis associating the Goddess speech in the Poem to a particular kind of oracle, similar
to that of the mantic healer. Such associations or assemblages, nonetheless, are not simple reproductions
of aspects already present in Greek culture: they are, as a matter of fact, subverted
in the direction of the philosophically instituted radical reflection, which collects signals from
visible and invisible, leading to thinking / Como é bem sabido, o poema de Parmênides, considerado uma das obras fundamentais
do pensamento filosófico grego, apresenta uma pluralidade de elementos míticos, seu esclarecimento
constituindo um problema para os intérpretes. Trata-se, neste trabalho, de
investigar o significado histórico-filosófico do mythos e do logos no poema, a partir da inserção
da obra em seus contextos culturais. Nossa análise inicia-se destacando a presença
do mythos, entendido em seu sentido original de maneira autorizada de falar, mostrando-o
de tal modo entrelaçado ao logos que o argumento , sem ele, sequer seria compreensível.
De outro lado, procuramos determinar a especificidade do logos de Parmênides: trata-se
de um logos reflexivo, refutativo , mas não, como pretendem alguns intérpretes, de uma
estrita demonstração . Estabelecido esse ponto, surge a obra de Parmênides como produtora
de agenciamentos míticos diversos, apropriando-se das imagens do poeta tradicional
inspirado, da iniciação nos cultos de mistérios, de figuras de divindades e da concepção da
existência humana presente na Lírica arcaica, efetuando-se o poema em múltiplas configurações discursivas (narrativa, argumento, fala oracular). Nesse sentido, introduzimos a
hipótese interpretativa da associação da fala da deusa no poema a um tipo específico de oráculo,
similar ao do médico-adivinho. Tais associações ou agenciamentos, todavia, não se
revelam como simples reproduções de aspectos presentes na cultura grega: eles são mesmo
subvertidos em direção à instauração filosófica de uma reflexão radical, que recolhe sinais
do visível e do invisível, conduzindo ao pensar
|
3 |
The Tension between Art and Science in Historical Writing.Depew, Michael Lee 16 August 2005 (has links)
A perennial question in the philosophy of history is whether history is a science or an art. This thesis contests that this question constitutes a false dichotomy, limiting the discussion in such a way as to exclude other possibilities of understanding the nature of the historical task.
The speculative philosophies of Augustine, Kant, and Marx; the critical philosophies of Ranke, Comte along with the later positivist, and the historical idealist such as Collingwood will be surveyed. History is then examined along side art to discuss not only the similarities but, the differences.
Major similarities—narrative presentation, emplotation, and the selective nature of historical evidence—between history and fiction are critiqued. A word study of the Greek word ίστοριά will show the essential difference between history and literature. The essential nature of the historical task can best be revealed in the differences between history and art.
|
4 |
The environment and natural rightsOsigwe, Uchenna W. 04 January 2005
The argument advanced is this thesis is that the entities that make up the environment are those that do not owe their origin to any willful creative activity but have evolved through accidental natural processes. This fact of not being willfully created makes the environment ontologically independent and confers on it intrinsic value as opposed to instrumental value. This intrinsic value is one that all the entities that make up the environment share. It is further argued that this intrinsic value is aesthetic rather than moral. Only beings that are specially endowed with certain capacities, like reflection and understanding, could be said, in the context of this work, to have intrinsic moral value in the sense of being moral agents. But as moral agents, we need to give moral considerability to all the natural entities in the environment since they share the same natural right with us, based on our common origin. So, even though the nonhuman, natural entities in the environment do not have moral rights, they have natural rights. It is further argued that this natural right could be best safeguarded in a legal framework.
|
5 |
The environment and natural rightsOsigwe, Uchenna W. 04 January 2005 (has links)
The argument advanced is this thesis is that the entities that make up the environment are those that do not owe their origin to any willful creative activity but have evolved through accidental natural processes. This fact of not being willfully created makes the environment ontologically independent and confers on it intrinsic value as opposed to instrumental value. This intrinsic value is one that all the entities that make up the environment share. It is further argued that this intrinsic value is aesthetic rather than moral. Only beings that are specially endowed with certain capacities, like reflection and understanding, could be said, in the context of this work, to have intrinsic moral value in the sense of being moral agents. But as moral agents, we need to give moral considerability to all the natural entities in the environment since they share the same natural right with us, based on our common origin. So, even though the nonhuman, natural entities in the environment do not have moral rights, they have natural rights. It is further argued that this natural right could be best safeguarded in a legal framework.
|
Page generated in 0.0622 seconds