• Refine Query
  • Source
  • Publication year
  • to
  • Language
  • 2335
  • 761
  • 431
  • 387
  • 247
  • 183
  • 89
  • 79
  • 59
  • 56
  • 53
  • 32
  • 32
  • 23
  • 22
  • Tagged with
  • 5513
  • 1641
  • 890
  • 769
  • 767
  • 616
  • 503
  • 407
  • 380
  • 372
  • 359
  • 338
  • 338
  • 320
  • 316
  • About
  • The Global ETD Search service is a free service for researchers to find electronic theses and dissertations. This service is provided by the Networked Digital Library of Theses and Dissertations.
    Our metadata is collected from universities around the world. If you manage a university/consortium/country archive and want to be added, details can be found on the NDLTD website.
131

Can lessons from game theory be applied to family law negotiations?

O'Hanlon, Johanne Elizabeth. January 2006 (has links)
The author suggests using lessons from Game Theory to improve the negotiation process and to construct more fitting agreements upon the breakdown of the family unit in the cases of separation or divorce. Currently many settlement agreements are inappropriate for the parties for a variety of reasons, including not establishing the parties' true interests during the negotiations. Furthermore, an inappropriate agreement may not be reopened by the court, given strict procedural and jurisprudential requirements. Game Theory lessons promote communication, cooperation, and forgiveness without allowing either party to be manipulated. These elements, already found in Collaborative Law, favour incorporating the lessons from Game Theory into this negotiation process.
132

The effect of relative anxiety level on learning badminton skills using two contrasting instructional methods /

Ruckenstein, Michael January 1974 (has links)
No description available.
133

Rationality, uncertainty aversion and equilibrium concepts in normal and extensive form games

Rothe, Jörn January 1999 (has links)
This thesis contributes to a re-examination and extension of the equilibrium concept in normal and extensive form games. The equilibrium concept is a solution concept for games that is consistent with individual rationality and various assumptions about players' knowledge about the nature of their strategic interaction. The thesis argues that further consistency conditions can be imposed on a rational solution concept. By its very nature, a rational solution concept implicitly defines which strategies are non-rational. A rational player's beliefs about play by non-rational opponents should be consistent with this implicit definition of non-rational play. The thesis shows that equilibrium concepts that satisfy additional consistency requirements can be formulated in Choquet-expected utility theory, i.e. non-expected utility theory with non-additive or set-valued beliefs, together with an empirical assumption about players' attitude toward uncertainty. Chapter 1 introduces the background of this thesis. We present the conceptual problems in the foundations of game theory that motivate our approach. We then survey the decision-theoretic foundations of Choquet-expected utility theory and game-theoretic applications of Choquet-expected utility theory that are related to the present approach. Chapter 2 formulates this equilibrium concept for normal form games. This concept, called Choquet-Nash Equilibrium, is shown to be a generalization of Nash Equilibrium in normal form games. We establish an existence result for finite games, derive various properties of equilibria and establish robustness results for Nash equilibria. Chapter 3 extends the analysis to extensive games. We present the equivalent of subgame-perfect equilibrium, called perfect Choquet Equilibrium, for extensive games. Our main finding here is that perfect Choquet equilibrium does not generalize, but is qualitatively different from subgame-perfect equilibrium. Finally, in chapter 4 we examine the centipede game. It is shown that the plausible assumption of bounded uncertainty aversion leads to an 'interior' equilibrium of the centipede game.
134

Players' beliefs in extensive form games

Board, O. J. January 2003 (has links)
The epistemic program in game theory uses formal models of interactive reasoning to provide foundations for various game-theoretic solution concepts. Much of this work is based around the (static) Aumann structure model of interactive epistemology, but more recently dynamic models of interactive reasoning have been developed, most notably by Stalnaker (Economics and Philosophy 1996) and Battigalli and Siniscalchi (Journal of Economic Theory 1999), and used to analyze rational play in extensive form games. But while the properties of Aumann structures are well un- derstood, without a formal language in which belief and belief revision statements can be expressed, it is unclear exactly what are the properties of these dynamic models. In chapter 1, "Dynamic In- teractive Epistemology", we investigate this question by defining such a language. A semantics and syntax are presented, with soundness and completeness theorems linking the two. Chapter 2, "Algorithmic Characterization of Ratioalizability in Extensive Form Games", uses the framework of chapter 1 to construct a dynamic epistemic model for extensive form games, which generates a hierarchy of beliefs for each player over her opponents' strategies and beliefs, and tells us how those beliefs will be revised as the game proceeds. We use the model to analyze the implications of the assumption that the players possess common (true) belief in rationality, thus extending the concept of rationalizability to extensive form games. Chapter 3, "The Equivalence of Bayes and Causal Rationality in Games", takes as its starting point a seminal paper of Aumann (Econometrica 1987), which showed how the choices of rational players could be analyzed in a unified state space framework. His innovation was to include the choices of the players in the description of the states, thus abolishing Savage's distinction between acts and consequences. But this simplification comes at a price: Aumann's notion of Bayes ratio­ nality does not allow players to evaluate what would happen were they to deviate from their actual choices. We show how the addition of a causal structure to the framework enables us to analyze such counterfactual statements, and use it to introduce a notion of causal rationality. Under a plausible causal independence condition, the two notions are shown to be equivalent. If we are prepared to accept this condition we can dispense with the causal apparatus and retain Aumann's original framework. In chapter 4, "The Deception of the Greeks", it is argued that the standard model of an extensive form game rules out an important phenomenon in situations of strategic interaction: deception. Using examples from the world of ancient Greece and from modern-day Wall Street, we show how the model can be generalized to incorporate this phenomenon. Deception takes place when the action observed by a player is different from the action actually taken. The standard model does allow imperfect information (modeled by non-singleton information sets), but not deception: the actual action taken is never ruled out. Our extension of extensive form games relaxes the assumption that the information sets partition the set of nodes, so that the set of nodes considered possible after a certain action is taken might not include the actual node. We discuss the implications of this relaxation, and show that in certain games deception is inconsistent with common knowledge of rationality even along the backward induction path.
135

Shinty dies hard : "Scotland's national game" : a re-assessment and re-definition, with particular reference to its survival and development in the nineteenth century in Australia, Canada, England and Ireland

MacLennan, Hugh Donald January 1998 (has links)
An original bilingual (Gaelic-English) collection of vocabulary, nomenclature and terminology relating to shinty and hurling, with reference to other stick and ball games is included as the first element. The sources consulted in Scotland, Ireland, Canada and Australia provide the first synthesis of material available about shinty in the nineteenth century across four Continents. Shinty is set in its historical context, examining the evidence, literary and oral, in both Gaelic and English, linking the game to other sports and cultures. A source-based approach is used to produce an analytical and innovative examination of the importance of shinty in its pre-regulated era, principally in terms of New York celebration. The game is examined in a specifically cultural context detailing how it changed during the nineteenth century with its fluctuating fortunes in rural and urban environments compared and contrasted over time. "Shinty in Glasgow" details the historical provenance of shinty in the Gaelic capital of the Highlands; "Shinty in England" details the precise nature of the game beyond Hadrian's Wall; "Shinty in the Americas" has as its focus shinty's influence as cultural anchor in Canada, and the apparent progenitor of ice hockey; "Shinty in Australia" breaks new ground, disproving the current mythology surrounding the game in Australia, examining the extent to which shinty survived as part of the cultural baggage taken by Scottish emigrants in the nineteenth century. Two chapters on the modern game analyse the effects of World Wars and economic/demographic change on the game and assess the links which existed with the Irish game of hurling at a number of levels. Revisionary conclusions are offered about the extent to which shinty was played as a game in the nineteenth century; how it was played across Scotland and an assessment made of the legitimacy of the game's traditional claim to be "Scotland's national game".
136

Coalition structures

Diamantoudi, Effrosyni. January 2000 (has links)
The first chapter introduces the topic of coalition structures and stresses its importance and impact on game theory. Additionally, it presents and motivates the significance of the three following chapters. / The second chapter investigates how rational individuals partition themselves into different coalitions. We propose a notion that determines simultaneously the coalition structures that are likely to prevail in a game, as well as the feasible payoff configurations associated with them. Our solution concept is built in the spirit of von Neumann and Morgenstern stability, but it overcomes the overoptimism associated with it when employed in our context. Moreover, in doing so, we achieve consistency and resolve the problem of myopia embedded in previous notions. We prove existence for a general class of games, and investigate the efficiency of our solution. / The third chapter ascertains which partitions of players will emerge and what actions will these players choose under each partition, when they can negotiate with each other and their actions have externalities. Naturally, the environment is depicted by a normal form game. The solution is a collection of pairs, each consisting of a coalition structure and a strategy profile. Although this chapter addresses the same question the Ray and Vohra (1997) paper did, it does so in a manner that overcomes the problems embedded in their approach. In particular, we assume that once a coalition deviates it fears the worst, given that the non-members do the best for themselves. In doing so, we improve upon previous solution concepts (e.g. strong and coalition-proof Nash equilibria) by NOT assuming that all other players will stay put. Yet, unlike the Ray and Vohra approach, we do not endow the deviating coalition with the power of imposing its will on all of the other players. A general solution concept is defined and its properties (efficiency, etc.) and applications are discussed. / The fourth chapter analyzes cartel stability when firms are farsighted. It studies a price leadership model a la D'Aspremont et al. (1983), where the dominant cartel acts as a leader by determining the market price, while the fringe behaves competitively. According to D'Aspremont et al.'s notion of cartel stability, a firm will not remain in a cartel as long as it prefers the outcome where it is the only member leaving the cartel for the fringe. Such an approach implies that the firm is myopic since it ignores whether the outcome of its deviation is stable itself. Our notion captures foresight by employing a solution concept built in the spirit of von Neumann and Morgenstern stable set, yet adopting an indirect dominance a la Harsanyi. We show that there always exists a unique, non-empty set of stable cartels.
137

State translation in no-limit poker

Schnizlein, David 11 1900 (has links)
One way to create a champion level poker agent is to compute a Nash Equilibrium in an abstract version of the poker game. The resulting strategy is then used to play in the full game. With this approach, translation is required between the full and abstract games in order to use the abstract strategy. In limit poker this translation step is defined when the abstraction is chosen. However, when considering no-limit poker the translation process becomes more complicated. We formally describe the process of translation and investigate its consequences. We examine how the current method, hard translation, can result in exploitable agents and introduce a new probabilistic method, soft translation, that produces more robust players. We also investigate how switching between strategies with different underlying abstractions affects the performance of an agent.
138

Varieties in contest models

Park, Sung-Hoon. January 2005 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Wyoming, 2005. / Title from PDF title page (viewed on Nov. 5, 2007). Includes bibliographical references (p. 125-129).
139

Information, game theory and patch defence in the parasitic wasp Trissolcus basalis Wollaston (Hymenoptera : Scelionidae) /

Calbert, Gregory. January 1999 (has links) (PDF)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Adelaide, Dept. of Applied Mathematics, 1999. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 158-166).
140

A game theoretic analysis of adaptive radar jamming /

Bachmann, Darren John. January 2006 (has links)
Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of Melbourne, 2006. / Typescript. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 222-236).

Page generated in 0.033 seconds