Spelling suggestions: "subject:"aristotle -- ethics"" "subject:"aristotle -- athics""
1 |
Aristotle's view of human nature as a basis for ethical theory.Watt, Stephen John. January 1998 (has links)
Thesis (Ph. D.)--Open University. BLDSC no. DXN020381.
|
2 |
Good natured : a discussion of the relationship between human nature and the good lifeLeggett, Andrew S. January 2000 (has links)
No description available.
|
3 |
Aristotle's steps to virtueHamalainen, Hasse Joel January 2015 (has links)
How to become morally virtuous? Among the students of Aristotle, it is often assumed that the philosopher does not have a fully worked-out theoretical answer to this question. Some interpreters (e.g. Burnyeat 1980, most recently Curzer 2012) have, however, recognised that Aristotle may have a comprehensive theory of moral development. However, even those interpreters have made only scarce attempts to study Aristotle’s theory in connection with the questions about his moral psychology. Unlike Aristotle’s theory of moral development as such, several of those questions are among the most debated issues in current Aristotle scholarship - for example, whether we need reason to identify good actions or whether habituated non-rational affects suffice; what makes us responsible for our actions, and how the philosopher conceives the relationship between phronesis and moral motivation. In my thesis, I aim at connecting these important questions with Aristotle’s theory of moral development. I hope to show that this approach will yield a picture on which Aristotle’s theory is divisible into two steps that one has to choose to take in order to become morally virtuous. I argue first that identifying good ends, and actions, requires reason. In order to become morally responsible, a person has thus to develop a rational ability to identify good actions. I show that Aristotle’s term for such ability is synesis. The first step to virtue, I conclude, is to use this ability well, to choose to become virtuous and habituate one’s character into acting well. The second step is to acquire phronesis, understanding why good actions are good, to complement a habituated character. Developing of phronesis requires both considerable experience in acting well and philosophical teaching about ethics, but it is necessary for moral virtue. Although a finely-habituated person is invulnerable to akrasia with regard to pleasures even if he did not have phronesis, Aristotle allows, I show, that he might still be prone to impetuous akrasia, whereas phronimos could avoid akratic behaviour in any situation.
|
4 |
Moral virtue as voluntary choice in Aristotle's ethics.Sourouzian, Zareh Aram. January 1970 (has links)
No description available.
|
5 |
Moral virtue as voluntary choice in Aristotle's ethics.Sourouzian, Zareh Aram. January 1970 (has links)
No description available.
|
6 |
Character friendship and moral development in Aristotle's EthicsVakirtzis, Andreas January 2014 (has links)
In my thesis, I examine the role of character friendship for the agent’s moral development in Aristotle’s ethics. I contend that we should divide character friendship in two categories: a) character friendship between completely virtuous agents, and, b) character friendship between unequally developed, or, equally developed, yet not completely virtuous agents. Regarding the first category, I argue that this highest form of friendship provides the opportunity for the agent to advance his understanding of certain virtues through the help of his virtuous friend. This process can be expressed in two ways. In the first way, I take character friendship in (a) as a relationship that is based on mutual relinquishing of opportunities for action or giving up external goods based on each agent’s needs. This process helps the agents develop their character in certain virtues which have remained slightly underdeveloped than others due to nature (NE 1144b4-7), or development (Politics 1329a9ff). This means, for instance, that if agent A is wealthy and his friend B is a middle class worker and they win the lottery together, A will relinquish his share of money to his friend so that he will be able to practice the virtue of magnificence; a virtue that his previous financial condition prevented him from developing appropriately. The second process is rather different and new in scholarly debate concerning Aristotle’s theory of moral development. I suggest that the completely virtuous agent is able to further develop his character through a process I will describe as interpretative mimesis. In this process, the agent receives the form of his friend’s action and is able to apply this pattern of behaviour in a situation that he thinks is appropriate. I have to highlight though the fact the fact that he does not just ape his friend’s action. Instead, he interprets the action based on his skills and abilities and the demands of the situations he faces. Thus, this pattern works as an extra epistemological tool in the agent’s hand in new and challenging moral situations. Now, case (b) comes on the opposite side of the majority of scholars’ view on character friendship. They think that Aristotle reserves character friendship only for completely virtuous agents. I argue that this is not the correct approach, and that less than completely virtuous agents can take part in character friendships as well. This view has the advantage of making character friendship in (b) a tool in Aristotle’s hands for his agents of lower moral level to develop their understanding of virtue and its applications. I propose that the route of moral development in case (b) resembles the one in the second process of case (a). Namely, the agent receives the form of his friend’s action and uses it as a pattern in some new situation he has to face. I will not name the process though as “interpretative” or any kind of mimesis. The reason for this is that Aristotle gives us textual evidence (NE 1172a9-14) for an imitative method of moral development only for the second process of case (a). I will take case (b) then as a pattern guide application of my friend’s action which we could call pre-interpretative mimesis period of the agent’s moral development. If my arguments are correct then character friendship is much more valuable than scholars thought. Our friends turn out to be examples of good action who guide us through the sweaty and painful path that is called virtue. And this path never stops; even if we have become “moral heroes”; or, put it differently, “masters” of practical wisdom.
|
7 |
Arisotelian and Confucian cultures of authority : justifying moral norms by appeal to the authority of exemplary personsHarris, Thorian Rane January 2005 (has links)
Thesis (M.A.)--University of Hawaii at Manoa, 2005. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 102-106). / vi, 106 leaves, bound 29 cm
|
8 |
Comparison of Nicomachean ethics and the ethics of Confucius : appropriateness of moral decisions /Wong, Kin Keung. January 2009 (has links)
Thesis (Ph.D.)--Hong Kong University of Science and Technology, 2009. / Includes bibliographical references (p. 133-137).
|
9 |
Aristotelův koncept morálně politické ekonomie / Aristotle's Concept of Morally Political EconomicsWEIS, František January 2014 (has links)
The paper is concerned with the question, if Aristotle among the other scientifical areas dealt also with the economics. The first part is mainly an introduction to the historical context. The second part explaines the economical passages from Nicomachean Ethics, and the third part analyses several key terms from the economical passages in Politics (oikos, oikonomike, chrematistike). In the end is the paper focused on the contrast between Aristotle's notion of oikonomike and the modern economics.
|
10 |
Aristotle's ethics, politics and economics : a philosophy of human affairs for the 22nd centuryTaylor, Tristen 27 August 2014 (has links)
D.Litt. et Phil. (Philosophy) / Please refer to full text to view abstract
|
Page generated in 0.0407 seconds