Spelling suggestions: "subject:"normativity"" "subject:"formativity""
51 |
Teleofunctionalism and the Normativity of Practical RationalityDiDomenico, David 12 August 2014 (has links)
In this thesis, I apply teleofunctionalism to a current debate concerning the normativity of practical rationality. Assuming teleofunctionalism is the correct theory of mental phenomena, I argue that it can provide a promising account of the normativity of practical rationality. This claim is motivated by the idea that a capacity to represent internal states, external states, and relations between these states as reasons for action has a teleofunction, and is thus a source of normativity. This teleofunction is marked by a distinctive causal role that reason-representation plays in action. Although I argue that this capacity developed out of processes of biological natural selection, the content of representations of reasons for action produced by the mechanisms underlying this capacity need not be determined solely by biological selection. In an effort to naturalize normativity in this way, I discuss the relation between biological-functional normativity and the normativity of rationality itself.
|
52 |
Karriärist javisst! : En kvalitativ studie om fäders upplevelser kring vård av barnJohansson, Lina, Pierre, Melissa January 2014 (has links)
Following is a study of fathers 'experiences of balance between work and home life. The method the researchers used was based on qualitative interviews aimed at describing father’s own experiences and values, which affects them. The researchers chose to specifically study situations where the fathers were faced with situations where their children needed to be cared for in the home because of a cold or similar illness since this is a situation that directly affects the time that was meant for work, but now risk being moved to areas of life that the researchers define as home life. This is to see whether the respondents felt that this situation affected the balance between work- and home life. The result shows that there are many values of masculinity and fatherhood that influence the respondents when they create their identities. It is those values that come into conflict, as different roles floats into other areas of life, which results in an imbalance between work- and home life. This means that fathers experience distress as they try to compensate by working from home or at other times. It also creates a conflict in ideal gender-equal relationships in which men and women in theory, try to act on values of gender-equality but in practice, solve these situation based on traditional gender patterns.
|
53 |
Location, Location, Location: An Alternative View Concerning the Location of the Deduction in Kants Third CritiqueTuna, Emine Hande 06 1900 (has links)
The project of the Critique of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment consists in providing a ground for judgments of taste so that we are justified in claiming that everybody else can agree with our judgment (subjective universality) and that all others ought to agree with us (subjective necessity, normativity). This justification is supposed to be accomplished in the Deduction of judgments of taste. The section that carries this title (38) is surprisingly short and for this and various other reasons (some of them textual) commentators have often wondered about the precise location where Kant provides the deduction, whether it is really contained in that short paragraph or whether the argument might actually extend beyond 38. In my thesis, I want to reinvigorate the discussion about the location of the deduction and its interpretation by arguing that it takes place between 30-42.
|
54 |
Arisotelian and Confucian cultures of authority : justifying moral norms by appeal to the authority of exemplary personsHarris, Thorian Rane January 2005 (has links)
Thesis (M.A.)--University of Hawaii at Manoa, 2005. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 102-106). / vi, 106 leaves, bound 29 cm
|
55 |
Kant's departure from Hume's moral naturalism : a thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy /Saunders, Joe. January 2007 (has links)
Thesis (M.A.)--University of Canterbury, 2007. / Typescript (photocopy). Includes bibliographical references (p. 89-90). Also available via the World Wide Web.
|
56 |
An examination of expressivist accounts of normative objectivity and motivationCarroll, Jing-yi, Catherine. January 2008 (has links)
Thesis (M. Phil.)--University of Hong Kong, 2009. / Includes bibliographical references (p. 92-96) Also available in print.
|
57 |
Ethics and artificial persons : structural impediments to ethical behavior in modern information media /Rowland, Wade. January 2004 (has links)
Thesis (Ph.D.)--York University, 2004. Graduate Programme in Communication and Culture. / Typescript. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 197-203). Also available on the Internet. MODE OF ACCESS via web browser by entering the following URL: http://wwwlib.umi.com/cr/yorku/fullcit?pNQ99232
|
58 |
Gender royalty : kings, queens, patriarchs, and the duke; queering normativity through the performance of gender /Ruchti, Elizabeth A. January 2006 (has links)
Thesis (Ph.D.)--Ohio University, June, 2006. / Includes bibliographical references (leaves 225-238)
|
59 |
A noção de esfera pública, seu carater normativo e seu desdobramento na filosofia de Jürgen Habermas.Menezes, Ilca Santos de January 2008 (has links)
110f. / Submitted by Suelen Reis (suziy.ellen@gmail.com) on 2013-04-16T16:21:13Z
No. of bitstreams: 1
Dissertacao Ilca Menezesseg.pdf: 651126 bytes, checksum: 7317e68c70bdedb293ee0c1dd982092d (MD5) / Approved for entry into archive by Rodrigo Meirelles(rodrigomei@ufba.br) on 2013-05-11T15:20:56Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1
Dissertacao Ilca Menezesseg.pdf: 651126 bytes, checksum: 7317e68c70bdedb293ee0c1dd982092d (MD5) / Made available in DSpace on 2013-05-11T15:20:56Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1
Dissertacao Ilca Menezesseg.pdf: 651126 bytes, checksum: 7317e68c70bdedb293ee0c1dd982092d (MD5)
Previous issue date: 2008 / A esfera pública é um tema polêmico. Desde sua origem na sociedade burguesa, o ideal de espaço discursivo e deliberativo, em que todos podem participar, fazendo uso de uma razão esclarecida, exercendo influência sobre o sistema político, é fundamental para a democracia. Mas há grupos excluídos, e a mídia de massa, que exerce influência sobre a opinião pública, com freqüência atende a interesses privados, provenientes de grupos, partidos políticos, e pessoas com poder econômico e de influência. Na sociedade contemporânea, essas questões críticas permanecem e a democracia precisa de seus fundamentos básicos. Em vista disso, Habermas pretende reabilitar o conceito de esfera pública, na complexa sociedade. Ele nunca abandona a questão do caráter normativo da comunicação pública esclarecida em relação à integração social e ao controle das ações políticas. As teorias da ação comunicativa e da ética do discurso, em Habermas, valorizam a racionalidade comunicativa, inerente à esfera pública. Essa racionalidade tem potencial normativo para a auto-regulação dos sujeitos e também para a manutenção da ordem social, porque as leis são fundamentadas através do discurso argumentativo. Habermas teoriza sobre a relação entre a normatividade da comunicação intersubjetiva e o sistema de direitos, do Estado democrático, que exerce controle sobre a sociedade civil e o Estado. A política democrática deliberativa surge dessa relação, e configura, na sociedade contemporânea, o ideal de esfera pública. / Salvador
|
60 |
O que é seguir uma regra? Reflexões filosóficas sobre normatividade / What is following a rule? Philosophical reflections on normativityMagalhães, Tiago de Oliveira January 2017 (has links)
MAGALHÃES, Tiago de Oliveira. O que é seguir uma regra? Reflexões filosóficas sobre normatividade. 2017. 127f. Tese (Doutorado) - Universidade Federal do Ceará, Instituto de Cultura e Arte, Programa de Pós-graduação em Filosofia, Fortaleza (CE), 2017. / Submitted by sebastiao barroso (jrwizard2209@hotmail.com) on 2017-09-11T13:16:23Z
No. of bitstreams: 1
2017_tese_tomagalhães.pdf: 899067 bytes, checksum: 9c077803fde4c382ebb5491cd4801e34 (MD5) / Approved for entry into archive by Márcia Araújo (marcia_m_bezerra@yahoo.com.br) on 2017-09-11T16:31:47Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1
2017_tese_tomagalhães.pdf: 899067 bytes, checksum: 9c077803fde4c382ebb5491cd4801e34 (MD5) / Made available in DSpace on 2017-09-11T16:31:48Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1
2017_tese_tomagalhães.pdf: 899067 bytes, checksum: 9c077803fde4c382ebb5491cd4801e34 (MD5)
Previous issue date: 2017 / This thesis approach the question contained in its title, taking as starting point the works of
Ludwig Wittgenstein and other authors related to him. In the first chapter, different aspects of
Wittgenstein’s conception of philosophy are evaluated. In the second chapter, it is argued that
rules should be understood as reasons and that only beings endowed with some form of
knowledge and capable of intentional behavior can follow them. Without appealing to the
capacity to adopt sapient normative positions, it is not possible to make the fundamental
distinction between following and merely conforming to a rule. Chapters III and IV deal
directly with problems canonically formulated in Saul Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and
Private Language. The communitarian conception defended by this author is criticized,
mainly through considerations on the distinction between public and private. It follows from
this that belonging to a community is not a necessary condition to be a rule-follower. As a
more appropriate solution to Kripke's skeptic challenge, the characterization of rule-following
as a specific ability to see aspects of action itself is pointed out. This capacity is constitutive
of symbolic language and, therefore, logically prior to it, so that to follow a rule it is not
necessary to master a language, understood in the strict sense. Finally, in the light of these
reflections, metaphilosophical arguments discussed in the first chapter are taken up and
expanded in order to substantiate the rejection of the quietist conception espoused by
Wittgenstein. / A pergunta que dá título a este trabalho é muito atual e também muito antiga, de maneira que
diversas tradições, perpassando numerosas áreas do conhecimento, estão disponíveis para
aquele que se propõe a abordá-la. Opta-se, aqui, pelo debate filosófico que tem Ludwig
Wittgenstein como principal referência. No primeiro capítulo, são indicados quais aspectos da
concepção de filosofia de Wittgenstein são, no restante da exposição, mantidos e quais são
descartados ou apenas parcialmente aceitos. No segundo capítulo, defende-se que regras
devem funcionar como razões e que apenas seres dotados de alguma forma de saber e capazes
de comportamento intencional podem segui-las. Sem apelar à capacidade de adotar posturas
normativas sapientes, não é possível realizar a distinção fundamental entre seguir e
meramente conformar-se a uma regra. Os capítulos III e IV lidam diretamente com problemas
canonicamente formulados no seminal Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, de Saul
Kripke. A concepção comunitarista defendida por esse autor é criticada, sobretudo através de
considerações sobre a distinção entre público e privado. Conclui-se, a partir delas, que
pertencer a uma comunidade não é condição necessária para ser um seguidor de regras, apesar
de ser uma propriedade muito relevante de todos os seguidores de regras conhecidos. Apontase,
como solução mais apropriada ao desafio cético de Kripke, a caracterização do seguimento
de regra como uma capacidade específica de ver aspectos da própria ação. Essa capacidade é
constitutiva da linguagem simbólica e, portanto, logicamente anterior a ela, de maneira que
para seguir regra não é necessário dominar uma linguagem em sentido estrito. Por fim, à luz
dessas reflexões, argumentos metafilosóficos discutidos no primeiro capítulo são retomados e
expandidos com o objetivo de fundamentar a rejeição da concepção quietista defendida por
Wittgenstein.
|
Page generated in 0.0801 seconds